Federal agencies use cost–benefit analysis to evaluate major regulations with life-or-death consequences—regulations that affect the air we breathe, the cars we drive, and the risks we face every day in our homes and workplaces. Historically, agency cost–benefit analysis has been color-blind and income blind: agencies have tallied up and compared costs and benefits without regard to the race, ethnicity, or financial status of the individuals affected. But on day one of his presidency, Joe Biden sought to inaugurate a new approach to regulatory review that reorients cost–benefit analysis around considerations of equity. In one of his first acts after taking the oath of office, President Biden issued a memorandum ordering officials in his new administration to produce “concrete suggestions on how the regulatory review process can promote”—among other values—“racial justice.”1 While Presidents Clinton and Obama previously called on agencies to give greater attention to distributive impacts in regulation, those calls proved largely hortatory. President Biden’s choice to make equitable cost–benefit analysis a priority as a day-one agenda item signals a new commitment to refashioning regulatory review into a redistributive mechanism.

So far, the Biden administration’s efforts to incorporate racial justice and other distributional considerations into cost–benefit analysis have not yet come to full fruition. Reviewing a sample of proposed and final rules promulgated by four agencies after two years of Biden’s presidency, Ricky Revesz and Burçin Ünel observed that agencies’ analysis of distributional considerations generally had been “truncated,” “inconsistent,” “inadequate,” or—a third of the time—nonexistent.2 But although Biden’s day-one memorandum has not yet transformed regulatory practice, it has encouraged scholars of regulation to give greater attention to the interactions among racial justice, economic inequality, and cost–benefit analysis.3 Daniel Farber’s lead article in this issue is a generative contribution to a fast-growing literature on cost–benefit analysis’s distributional dimensions.

Farber makes two big claims. First, he argues that agency cost–benefit analysis already embeds distributional concerns in ways that have largely escaped scholarly notice. In particular, he points to the fact that agencies assign the same “value of a statistical life” (VSL) to all Americans, notwithstanding economic theory and evidence indicating that willingness to pay for mortality risk reduction varies by income. “Compared with the economically ‘correct’ approach of using lower values for the poor,” Farber writes, the use of population average VSLs for individuals with below-average income “amounts to a degree of redistribution in their favor.”4 Farber primarily emphasizes the implications of equal-dollar VSLs for redistribution across income groups, but as Farber notes, the economic and racial dimensions of inequality are “interrelated”5: the use of population-average VSLs rather than income-adjusted VSLs results in higher values for the lives of low-income individuals and, in the aggregate, higher values for the lives of African Americans, Latinos, and Native Americans (i.e., groups with lower average incomes). And Farber not only highlights VSL equality, he celebrates it. Whereas other scholars have viewed the use of equal-dollar VSLs as “a pragmatic adjustment to uninformed public attitudes,” Farber argues instead that the use of equal-dollar VSLs “embodies a distinctive vision of equality” under which “individuals have equal entitlements to protection against harm, regardless of wealth or other personal characteristics.”6

Second, Farber argues that federal agencies should consider the racially disparate impacts of regulatory costs and benefits when crafting their rules. He specifically advances a Hippocratic principle for racial justice in regulation—“first, do no harm”7—that he excavates from a close reading of President Clinton’s ambitious but largely unrealized 1994 executive order on environmental justice.8 According to the Hippocratic criterion, agencies should evaluate proposed regulations for each racial and ethnic group against the baseline of the status quo. If a regulation leaves a disadvantaged group worse off than the baseline, the agency should seek to mitigate the disparate impact.9

I agree with much of Farber’s analysis. Like Farber, I believe that agencies have compelling practical reasons to use equal-dollar VSLs, though as I have explained at length elsewhere, I do not think the issue can be resolved on moral egalitarian grounds: regulatory cost–benefit analysis could assign different dollar values to different individuals’ lives and still accord equal weight to everyone’s interests.10 Like Farber, I also think that presidents should use executive action—including action through agencies such as the Environmental Protection Agency (EPA) and the Department of Transportation—to advance racial justice aims, at least when more direct transfer mechanisms are politically, judicially, or practically foreclosed. But unlike Farber, I recognize a deep tension between the argument for equal-dollar VSLs and the argument for disparate-impact analysis in regulatory decision-making—a tension that resists easy resolution.

The tension is this: To know whether a regulation benefits or burdens a particular group on net, we must calculate benefits and costs using willingness-to-pay numbers for that particular group, not for the population at large. Because willingness to pay for mortality risk reduction varies by income, disparate-impact analysis for mortality risk regulation also must use VSLs that vary by income. And because income varies by race, disparate impact analysis requires that average VSLs also differ by race (or that analysts make other adjustments that are arithmetically equivalent to the use of race-differential VSLs). Farber appears to acknowledge this point in the context of “equity weighting,” a methodology that incorporates distributional considerations into cost–benefit analysis by explicitly assigning greater numerical weights to benefits and costs accruing to lower income or disadvantaged groups. “To use equity weighting properly,” Farber writes, “we should abandon the use of fixed dollar values on life.”11 But the point applies well beyond equity weighting—it holds true across the board for distributional analysis of lifesaving regulations. And if regulators attempted to abandon equal-dollar VSLs, they would likely encounter a range of risks and challenges that are much more daunting than Farber anticipates. The limited available evidence suggests that even very well-informed observers quickly fall into the habit of thinking that lower-dollar VSLs imply lesser regard for the people to whom those lower dollar values are applied. This reaction is understandable—Americans are, after all, used to thinking about value in dollar terms—and it is hard to shake even when the overall analysis accords greater weight to the interests of the people to whom lower-dollar VSLs are assigned. The danger in using different dollar VSLs for groups with different average incomes is not just the danger of a public relations disaster—it is the danger of sending a message of disrespect to the very people whose interests equitable cost–benefit analysis seeks to vindicate.

I will call this the equality–equity dilemma in cost–benefit analysis, with “equality” referring to the use of equal-dollar VSLs and “equity” referring to the use of cost–benefit analysis to pursue distributional objectives. If we are committed to advancing equity through cost–benefit analysis, then we must give up on equal-dollar VSLs (or make arithmetic adjustments with similar effects, but abandoning equal-dollar VSLs runs the risk of triggering a popular backlash and—beyond that—of generating serious expressive harms. My goal in this short comment is (1) to show why the equality–equity dilemma arises and (2) to sketch out several possible paths that regulators might take in response. The comment concludes with reflections on what the equality–equity dilemma can teach us about the broader cost–benefit analysis enterprise.

A. Defining “Equality” and “Equity”

“Equality” and “equity” are chameleonic terms: they take on different meanings and shades depending upon speaker and context. As Martha Minow has observed, the terms are often deployed as “weapons in polarized political arguments rather than analytical tools.”12 To use these terms as analytical tools, we must first settle on provisional definitions of each.

“Equality,” in the sense that I invoke it here, refers specifically to VSL equality—the use of equal-dollar VSLs across individuals and groups. “Equity,” for its part, will serve as shorthand for the goal of making members of disadvantaged groups “better off” in the standard welfare sense: policy makers advance equity when they achieve outcomes that members of disadvantaged groups rationally prefer over the status quo. My argument here is that to determine whether policies make members of disadvantaged groups better off in a standard welfare sense, we will need to set strict adherence to VSL equality to the side.

To be sure, the particular conceptions of equality and equity that I invoke here are far from the only possible operationalizations of those terms. Elsewhere in this issue, David Weisbach notes that instead of VSL equality, we might conceive of equality in terms of respect. Equality of respect—or “respect egalitarianism”—“respects all individuals … equally by taking their views into account, including their risk versus return tradeoffs as measured empirically by their VSLs.”13 So conceived, equality of respect would require policy makers to honor the risk trade-offs that individuals rationally make in the real world. The use of equal-dollar VSLs would violate the equality-of-respect principle “because it implies, indeed explicitly states, that [lower income individuals’] well-informed views on matters about their own life are wrong.”14 Weisbach presents the equality-of-respect concept not to advocate for it but to illustrate that appeals to “equality” do not resolve the debate of VSL differentiation. Ultimately, all claims of equality must answer the question posed by Amartya Sen in the title of his seminal Tanner Lecture: “equality of what?”15 Rather than try to answer that question here, I will try to show that Farber’s own operationalization of equality—the use of equal-dollar VSLs—collides with other normative objectives that distributional cost–benefit analysis aims to advance.

“Equity,” for its part, encounters a similar Sen-like equity-of-what question. Following Farber, I will take as a given that agencies, when making regulatory decisions, ought to give additional weight, formally or informally, to the welfare of disadvantaged individuals and groups. Also like Farber, this comment will interpret disadvantage in both economic and racial/ethnic terms. The examples below leverage sources that report relevant data for African Americans and Latinos, but my focus on those groups is not meant to suggest that the aims of distributional cost–benefit analysis are limited to those groups. The same analysis would apply to any group with average incomes below the population average (e.g., Native Americans).

In line with the overall cost–benefit analysis enterprise, I will interpret welfare in terms of preferences: an individual’s welfare is higher under outcome A than under outcome B if the individual would prefer A to B (i.e., would give up something of nonzero value to switch from B to A). A preference-focused measure of welfare can be framed in monetary willingness-to-pay terms, but the use of a money metric does not mean that money is all that matters. As Cass Sunstein has observed, a willingness-to-pay measure of welfare “honors qualitatively diverse goods that people care about for diverse reasons.”16 Below, I will consider an alternative measure of welfare that gets at the same concept without using money as the metric.17 For now, the key point is that “equity” in the equality–equity dilemma refers to the goal of making members of disadvantaged groups better off in conventional welfare terms.

Again, this is not the only possible way to define “equity.” We could, among other alternatives, define “equity” in terms that refer only one side of the cost–benefit equation. For example, we might imagine someone saying that a motor vehicle safety regulation advances racial equity if it reduces African American vehicle fatalities—or if it reduces the relative or absolute disparity between African American and white vehicle fatality rates. However, cost–benefit analysis reflects the sensible premise that costs and benefits ought to be weighed against each other—not all regulations that provide benefits remain “worth it” once we account for costs. And if that is true at the population level, it would seem to be true at the subgroup level as well: If we genuinely care about the well-being of disadvantaged groups, we should evaluate policies based on both the costs and the benefits accruing to members of those disadvantaged groups. Otherwise, we might end up—in the ostensible name of equity—adopting policies that leave members of those groups worse off.

B. Income, Race, and the Value of a Statistical Life

The conflict between equality and equity—“equality” again referring to VSL equality and “equity” referring to the goal of making members of disadvantaged groups better off in conventional welfare terms—arises in the context of regulatory decisions that require trade-offs between lives and dollars. This dollars-versus-lives question is ubiquitous in federal regulation: according to one estimate, seventy percent of the total benefits of major federal regulations are “directly attributable to the monetized value of reducing early mortality.”18 For air quality standards promulgated by the EPA, the proportion of benefits attributable to lives saved is even higher: the EPA estimates that eighty-five percent of the monetized benefits of Clean Air Act regulations from 1990 to 2020 stem from reductions in premature mortality related to one type of pollutant—particulate matter.19 In very broad brushstrokes, saving lives is what most high-cost federal regulations do.20

When federal agencies are deciding whether to promulgate regulations that impose economic costs in pursuit of lifesaving benefits, they need a mechanism for comparing dollars to lives. Across the regulatory state, the “value of a statistical life” serves as that mechanism. The VSL is, formally, the amount of money that individuals are willing to exchange for a small change in mortality risk divided by the change in mortality risk. For example, if an individual is willing to pay $10 to avoid a 1-in-1-million risk of death, or willing to accept $10 for a 1-in-1-million increase in her risk of death, then her VSL is $10 million.21 Federal agencies derive their VSL figures primarily from wage-risk studies, which seek to estimate how much workers are compensated for taking higher-fatality-risk jobs. As of 2023, most federal agencies use a VSL of around $12 million when conducting cost–benefit analyses of lifesaving rules.22

Standard microeconomic theory suggests—and empirical analysis confirms23—that willingness to pay for mortality risk reduction increases with an individual’s income. The relationship between VSL and income arises not primarily because high-income individuals value their lives more but because they value their dollars less. Due to the diminishing marginal utility of income, an additional dollar of income for Jeff Bezos contributes much less to his well-being than an additional dollar of income contributes to your and my well-being. Thus, if Jeff Bezos derives the same utility from his life as you and I derive from our lives, but Jeff Bezos derives much less utility from an additional dollar than you and I derive from an additional dollar, then Jeff Bezos should demand more dollars in exchange for a given increase to his mortality risk than you and I would.

The relationship between income and VSL is reflected by a parameter known as the “income elasticity of the value of a statistical life.”24 The income elasticity of the VSL is the percent change in the VSL for a percent change in income. An income elasticity of 1 implies that when income rises by one percent, VSL rises by one percent (and similarly, when income doubles, VSL doubles). While federal agencies do not use the income elasticity of the VSL to differentiate among deaths averted in any given year, they rely on the income elasticity of the VSL to update the overall VSL from year to year.

Most federal agencies have converged on an income elasticity of the VSL equal to 1.25 An income elasticity of 1 corresponds to a condition known as “log utility,” in which the utility of income is the natural logarithm of total income. Because the first derivative of the natural logarithm of x is 1/x, log utility implies that the marginal utility of income is the inverse of total income. Thus, when income doubles, the marginal utility of income decreases by half. If someone with $50,000 of income values her life the same in utility terms as someone with $100,000 of income, but the person with $100,000 of income has half the marginal utility of income as the person with $50,000 of income, then the person with $100,000 of income should have twice the willingness to pay for mortality risk reductions (because she gets the same marginal utility from an additional $2 as the person with $50,000 of income gets from an additional $1).26

The income elasticity of the VSL is a critically important variable for estimating the distribution of regulatory benefits. Consider the example of passenger vehicle safety standards. African Americans experience a disproportionate share of passenger vehicle occupant fatalities in the United States: the passenger vehicle occupant fatality rate for African Americans in 2019 was approximately 8.1 per 100,000, versus 6.3 per 100,000 for non-Hispanic whites (see Table 1). Using the Department of Transportation’s 2019 VSL of $10.9 million,27 the monetized burden of passenger vehicle occupant fatalities for African Americans was approximately $881 per person, versus $691 per person for non-Hispanic whites. Thus, a regulation that reduced passenger vehicle occupant fatalities across the board would disproportionately benefit African Americans relative to whites. But this doesn’t account for the fact that mean household income for African Americans in 2019 was thirty-eight percent lower than mean household income for non-Hispanic whites. Adjusting VSL for income with an income elasticity of 1, the monetized burden of passenger vehicle occupant fatalities was higher for whites ($752 per person) than for African Americans ($598 per person).28 Using income-elastic VSLs, a regulation that reduced passenger vehicle fatalities across the board would disproportionately benefit whites relative to African Americans.

Table 1:

Distribution of Deaths and Monetized Mortality Burden for Passenger Vehicle Occupant Fatalities by Race and Ethnicity (2019)

Race/EthnicityPopulationDeathsRate (per 100,000)Average Household IncomeCosts/Person (Equal VSL)Costs/Person (Elastic VSL)
White, non-Hispanic 196,789,401 12,480 6.34 $106,659 $691 $752 
Black, non-Hispanic 40,596,040 3,281 8.08 $66,553 $881 $598 
Hispanic/Latino 60,481,746 3,985 6.59 $75,058 $718 $550 
Asian, non-Hispanic 18,427,914 252 1.37 $133,111 $149 $202 
Other/unknown — 2,374 — — — — 
Total/Average 328,239,523 (total) 22,372 (total) 6.82 (average) $98,088 (average) $743 (average) $716 (average) 
Race/EthnicityPopulationDeathsRate (per 100,000)Average Household IncomeCosts/Person (Equal VSL)Costs/Person (Elastic VSL)
White, non-Hispanic 196,789,401 12,480 6.34 $106,659 $691 $752 
Black, non-Hispanic 40,596,040 3,281 8.08 $66,553 $881 $598 
Hispanic/Latino 60,481,746 3,985 6.59 $75,058 $718 $550 
Asian, non-Hispanic 18,427,914 252 1.37 $133,111 $149 $202 
Other/unknown — 2,374 — — — — 
Total/Average 328,239,523 (total) 22,372 (total) 6.82 (average) $98,088 (average) $743 (average) $716 (average) 

Notes: “Costs/Person (Equal VSL)” based on 2019 Department of Transportation VSL of $10.9 million. “Costs/Person (Elastic VSL)” based on income elasticity of the VSL equal to 1.

Sources: Disparities by Race or Ethnic Origin, Natl Safety Council (2022), https://injuryfacts.nsc.org/motor-vehicle/road-users/disparities-by-race-or-ethnic-origin (2019 data); Historical Income Tables: Households tbl.H-5. Race and Hispanic Origin of Householder—Households by Median and Mean Income: 1967 to 2021, U.S. Census Bureau (2022), https://www.census.gov/data/tables/time-series/demo/income-poverty/historical-income-households.html (2019 data); American Community Survey: DP05|ACS Demographic and Housing Estimates: 2019—ACS 1-Year Estimates Data Profile, U.S. Census Bureau, https://data.census.gov/table?q=DP05&tid=ACSDP1Y2019.DP05 (last visited Feb. 14, 2023).

Population-average costs per person with income-elastic VSLs calculated by adding costs for reported demographic groups, imputing population-average household income to individuals in “Other/unknown,” and averaging over total U.S. population as of 2019.

To be clear, the only compelling reason to think that average VSLs vary across racial and ethnic groups is that average income varies across racial and ethnic groups. While some studies have considered whether VSL varies by race and ethnicity, the findings are inconsistent. For example, Kip Viscusi reported in a 2003 study that African American workers receive less additional compensation for performing high-fatality risk jobs than white workers, resulting in implied VSLs of $7 million to $9 million for African Americans versus $13 million to $15 million for whites.29 However, Viscusi concluded that it would be “inappropriate to attribute the observed differences to a greater willingness by black workers to bear risk.”30 Rather, Viscusi suggested that a “more likely” explanation lay in “structurally different labor market opportunities by race.”31 By contrast, from a 2010 study, James Hammitt and Kevin Haninger found that after controlling for income, African American survey respondents were willing to pay more for mortality risk reductions than non-Hispanic whites.32 However, Hammitt and Haninger’s experiment did not involve real money at stake, raising concerns about “hypothetical bias” (a phenomenon in which individuals report a higher willingness to pay in survey settings than in real-world settings).33 All in all, the evidence is too scant and inconsistent to conclude that there are any racial and ethnic differences in willingness to pay for mortality risk reduction except for differences attributable to income.

So far, we have focused only on the benefits side of the ledger, but a full distributional analysis requires consideration of the cost distribution as well. Even if African Americans receive a disproportionately small share of a regulation’s total benefits, they still may be among the regulation’s largest net beneficiaries if they also bear a disproportionately small share of regulatory costs. In the vehicle safety case, competing intuitions suggest that the share of costs borne by African Americans may be disproportionately low or disproportionately high relative to other groups. The average number of vehicles is lower for African American–headed households (1.38 as of 2009) than for households headed by non-Hispanic whites (1.99),34 so insofar as the costs of complying with safety regulations are passed through dollar-for-dollar to vehicle owners, African Americans are likely to bear less than their population-proportionate share of costs. On the other hand, higher-priced car models often incorporate new safety features before the National Highway Traffic Safety Administration (NHTSA) mandates fleetwide adoption. Therefore, lower-priced models generally are the ones most affected by new vehicle safety standards. Insofar as African Americans have lower average incomes and tend to buy lower-priced cars, they may bear more than their population-proportionate share of regulatory costs. And insofar as costs are passed through to shareholders and/or employees of automakers, African Americans may bear a disproportionately small share of costs (because they tend to hold less stock35) or a disproportionately large share (because they account for eighteen percent of the car manufacturing workforce versus just thirteen percent of the workforce writ large).36

Uncertainty about the distribution of costs remains even when (indeed, especially when) costs are borne in the first instance by the government. Imagine, for example, a safety-motivated roadway redesign project or an effort to install crash cushions on roadside objects that will reduce deaths in vehicle crashes while imposing a fiscal cost. If the expenditure is financed by higher income taxes on the rich, then most racial and ethnic minority groups will likely bear less than their population-proportionate share of the costs because most minority groups are underrepresented in the top income brackets. If the expenditure is financed by cuts to government programs that disproportionately benefit racial and ethnic minorities (e.g., Medicaid37), then racial and ethnic minorities will likely bear more than their population-proportionate share of the costs.38

Although ambiguity about the distribution of costs makes it difficult to say whether any particular vehicle safety regulation has a disparate impact on racial or ethnic minorities, the example of passenger vehicle safety serves to underscore two points. First, using a higher VSL for a particular group does not necessarily redound to the benefit of group members. For an area such as passenger vehicle safety, where the lives saved by more stringent standards are likely to come disproportionately from lower-income groups, using population-average VSLs rather than income-adjusted VSLs will predictably lead to higher benefit estimates and therefore stronger regulations. But stronger regulations do not necessarily benefit members of lower income groups.

This point is perhaps most easily illustrated through a simple numerical example. For expositional ease, I will use a hypothetical regulation with made-up numbers for fatality reductions and per-person costs but real-world numbers for VSL and income. For a real-world regulatory example in which assigning higher VSLs to lower income groups makes members of those groups worse off, interested readers can consult my analysis of NHTSA’s 2014 rear visibility rule.39

Our hypothetical regulation will reduce passenger vehicle fatalities by one percent across the board. Costs of $7.25 per person will be distributed evenly across the population (for example, because higher-income households buy more cars but lower-income households are more likely to buy cars affected by the safety regulation). Using the Department of Transportation’s actual population average VSL for 2019 ($10.9 million),40 the regulation would narrowly pass a cost–benefit test (benefit of $7.43 per person). Now imagine that we take into account the distribution of vehicle occupant deaths and household income across racial and ethnic groups and we use income-adjusted VSLs with an income elasticity of 1. In that case, the regulation would fail a cost–benefit test (benefit of $7.16 per person). Non-Hispanic whites would benefit, on average, from the regulation (benefit of $7.52 per person versus cost of $7.25). African Americans would be harmed, on average, from the regulation (benefit of $5.98 per person versus cost of $7.25). Here, a switch from income-adjusted VSLs to population-average VSLs would push the regulation over the breakeven threshold, and if the regulation were then adopted, non-Hispanic whites would benefit on net and African Americans would be harmed on net.

The example is, to be sure, highly stylized. One can imagine other cases in which a switch from income-adjusted VSLs to population-average VSLs might benefit African Americans.41 But as the example illustrates, Farber’s blanket statement that the use of population-average VSLs “amounts to a degree of redistribution in … favor”42 of lower income groups is not necessarily true. Indeed, we cannot even say that it is true in a more-likely-than-not sense.43 Theoretically, the effect of higher VSLs on lower-income groups is ambiguous, and the set of empirical studies that systematically assess the distributional effects of higher VSLs for lower-income groups is empty.44

Another way of framing the same point is this45: Most high-dollar-cost federal regulations—air quality standards, fuel economy standards, and vehicle safety standards46—entail a choice between more stringent and less stringent national rules. Agencies don’t, for example, have the statutory authority to adopt different air quality standards for predominantly African American and predominantly white neighborhoods: the Clean Air Act envisions that standards will be the same nationwide.47 Likewise, federal motor vehicle safety standards don’t depend upon the race or ethnicity of a vehicle’s driver (and it’s unclear how, as a practical matter, they even could, unless the federal government were to ban interracial sales of used cars, which would surely be both unconstitutional and undesirable). In the context of national standards, higher VSLs lead to higher estimates of total benefits and thus weigh in favor of more stringent rules, whether those higher values are assigned to higher-income or lower-income groups. Thus, in the motor vehicle safety example in Table 1, where the ratio of total African American deaths to total white deaths is 0.263 to 1,48 raising the VSL for African Americans by $1 has the same effect on estimated total benefits as raising the VSL for whites by 26.3 cents. In that context, it makes little more sense to say that “higher VSLs for African Americans redistribute in favor of African-Americans” than to say that “higher VSLs for whites redistribute in favor of African Americans.” Again, the practical effect of raising the African American VSL by $1 is the same as the practical effect of raising the white VSL by 26.3 cents. Either adjustment raises the total benefit estimate by the exact same amount.

Second, and of particular importance for the purposes of this comment, sensible distributional analysis requires income-adjusted VSLs. If the income elasticity of the VSL reflected irrational behavior by members of lower-income groups, perhaps paternalism would justify the use of equal-dollar VSLs. But there is nothing irrational about having a higher marginal utility of income when your income is low, and someone with a high marginal utility of income will generally be less willing to sacrifice income for risk reduction. Indeed, it would be quite puzzling if members of lower-income groups had the same willingness to pay for fatality risk reduction as higher income groups: it would call into question the bedrock assumption of declining marginal utility of income that underlies much of positive and normative economics. Moreover, as the vehicle-safety example illustrates, equal-dollar VSLs are not serviceable substitutes for income-adjusted VSLs in distributional analysis when average incomes differ significantly across groups. The use of equal-dollar VSLs rather than income-adjusted VSLs may mislead us into concluding that regulations benefit groups whom they harm.

C. The Risk of Abandoning Equal-Dollar VSLs

As far as I know, no scholar seriously advocates the use of equal-dollar VSLs in distributional analysis (at least, not without other adjustments that offset the effects of VSL equality).49 Farber himself says he is ready to “abandon the use of fixed-dollar values on life” in the context of “equity weighting,” a methodology in which analysts calculate costs and benefits separately for each distributionally relevant group and then apply a greater numerical weight to effects on worse-off groups when aggregating results.50 As the discussion above makes clear, less comprehensive forms of distributional analysis, such as the Hippocratic criterion, likewise require the abandonment of equal-dollar VSLs. Without income-adjusted VSLs, the Hippocratic criterion would potentially allow some actions that leave lower-income groups worse off while exerting a veto on some actions that make lower-income groups better off. The actual effects on the welfare of disadvantaged groups would be scattershot.

If everyone understood what Farber understands—and what readers who have reached this point also understand—then the equality–equity dilemma might be no dilemma at all: regulators evaluating the distributional impacts of proposed regulations could use income-adjusted VSLs uncomplicatedly. But the limited available evidence suggests that the public reaction to income-adjusted VSLs may differ rather dramatically from Farber’s, even when income-adjusted VSLs are used to advance equity objectives. That evidence comes from two sources: first, the academic literature on income-adjusted VSLs, and second, the “senior death discount” debacle at the EPA in the early 2000s.

First, a close reading of the academic literature on equity and cost–benefit analysis reveals that even very sophisticated scholars lapse into using language that suggests that lower-income groups benefit when policy makers assign them VSLs that exceed their willingness to pay. For example, Thomas Kniesner and Kip Viscusi—two of the world’s leading experts on the VSL—wrote in a recent working paper that “application of an equitable VSL provides a bonus subsidy to Blacks relative to whites of about 20% for the median worker.”51 By “bonus subsidy,” the authors simply mean that the median African American worker makes less than the median white worker, and therefore—as compared to the alternative of income-adjusted VSLs—use of equal-dollar VSLs boosts the VSL for the median African American worker relative to the median white worker. But the fact that even preeminent scholars describe higher VSLs as a “bonus subsidy” for individuals and groups to whom those higher values are assigned goes to show just how hard it will be to shake the idea that higher VSLs necessarily benefit—and lower VSLs necessarily harm—economically disadvantaged groups.

To be clear, Kniesner and Viscusi—who comprehend the intricacies of VSL estimates better than possibly anyone else alive, and who have contributed enormously and generously to my own understanding of VSL-related issues—certainly know that using higher VSLs for lower-income groups does not always provide a “bonus subsidy” to those groups in a welfare sense. Indeed, Kniesner and Viscusi stated that “when policy costs are borne privately, requiring levels of safety that are reflective of a VSL that is greater than that of affected groups will reduce their expected welfare levels.”52 And Kniesner and Viscusi are not the only scholars who (a) understand that higher VSLs don’t necessarily benefit lower-income groups but (b) use language that suggests otherwise. Farber, for his part, does the same. For example, Farber writes that “[a]gencies … elevate the interests of the poor by deviating from theory and treating the value of life as constant regardless of wealth.”53 Again, there is zero evidence to support that statement: no study shows that lower-income groups fare better when regulators apply equal-dollar VSLs rather than income-adjusted VSLs. By asking the general public to accept the abandonment of equal-dollar VSLs in distributional analysis, Farber is asking laypeople to understand that the use of income-adjusted VSLs does not operate to the detriment of lower-income groups in that context when Farber himself suggests (without evidence) that the use of equal-dollar VSLs operates to the benefit of lower-income groups in a related context.

To be sure, these two ideas—(a) that the use of equal-dollar VSLs doesn’t necessarily benefit lower-income groups in standard cost–benefit analysis and (b) that the use of equal-dollar VSLs wouldn’t necessarily benefit lower-income groups in distributional analysis—are distinct. I am critiquing Farber for disregarding (a), whereas Farber is asking laypeople to accept (b). It may be that (b) is much easier to comprehend, such that we can expect laypeople to understand (b) even when sophisticated scholars of regulation seem to ignore (a) in their academic writing. This would be asking a lot of the American people, but perhaps we can be Kennedy-esque about it and ask our fellow countrymen for a lot.

Unfortunately, the second source of evidence regarding the fallout from using different values for different groups—the “senior death discount” debacle at the EPA—does not lend itself to optimism about the public’s capacity to comprehend the nuances of the VSL. In the fall of 2002, EPA published two cost–benefit analyses that sought to monetize the benefits of reducing air pollution: a September 2002 “technical addendum” to the Bush administration’s “Clear Skies” legislative proposal54 and a November 2002 regulatory-impact analysis of a proposed rule regulating engine emissions.55 Both analyses included a “base estimate” using equal-dollar VSLs along with an “alternative estimate” that monetized mortality benefits using a “value of statistical life year” (VSLY) approach.56 Although the EPA’s alternative estimate did not differentiate on the basis of income, the public reaction to the EPA’s alternative estimate serves as a cautionary tale regarding future efforts to use income-adjusted VSLs.

In both the “Clear Skies” and engine-emissions analyses, the EPA observed that the people whose deaths are accelerated by exposure to particulate matter (PM) often suffer from other ailments, such as chronic obstructive pulmonary disease (COPD) and cardiovascular disease. In its alternative estimates, the EPA assumed that when reductions in air pollution prevent premature deaths, the individuals whose deaths are averted will live an additional five years (or six months if they suffer from COPD). To estimate values of a statistical life year for those individuals, the EPA took two tacks. First, for individuals under the age of 65, the EPA used a VSLY of $163,000. It arrived at the $163,000 figure by assuming that the VSL for a 40-year-old worker is $3.7 million in 1999 dollars and that the $3.7 million figure corresponds to 35 remaining years of life at a 3% discount rate. Second, for individuals over age 65, the EPA used a VSLY of $258,000. It arrived at that figure by assuming that the VSL for a 70-year-old is $2.3 million in 1999 dollars (a figure based on a study estimating that the VSL for a 70-year-old is 37% lower than the VSL for a 40-year-old) and that the $2.3 million figure corresponds to 10 years of remaining life at a 3% discount rate. Projecting forward to 2020 and updating values to reflect expected income growth, the EPA estimated that the value of delaying the death of a non-COPD sufferer under the age of 65 would be $1 million, while the value of delaying the death of a non-COPD sufferer over 65 would be $1.6 million. “Since we assume that there is a 5-year loss in life years for PM related mortality, regardless of the age of person dying, this necessarily leads to a lower VSL for younger populations,” the EPA stated.57

Notwithstanding the fact that the EPA’s alternative estimate implied that the value of averting a premature death for an individual over the age of 65 was 60% greater than the value for someone under 65, the Natural Resources Defense Council fired off an audacious press release charging that EPA’s alternative estimate “calculated the value of saving the life of a 65-year-old senior as being only worth 63 percent of a younger person’s life.”58 The popular press quickly picked up this highly misleading claim. “How could the Environmental Protection Agency decide that the life of someone over 70 years old is worth $1.4 million less than the life of a younger person?” a New York Times news analysis asked.59 EPA officials predictably ran into protests at hearings in California, Florida, Iowa, Pennsylvania, and Texas, where demonstrators sported stickers reading “Senior Discount: 37 Percent Off.” Responding to that backlash, EPA Administrator Christine Todd Whitman announced in May 2003 that the agency would drop the alternative estimate from future analyses.60

What can the senior death discount debacle tell us about the use of income-adjusted VSLs in distributional analysis? In the senior death discount case, the EPA used lower VSLs for seniors at an intermediate step in a calculation that ultimately put greater weight on seniors than on younger individuals whose lives would be extended by reduced exposure to air pollutants. Activists seized on the lower VSL for seniors, ignoring subsequent steps of the analysis, and media accounts failed to add context or nuance. Analogously, Farber and others propose to use lower VSLs for African Americans and other disadvantaged minorities at an intermediate step in a distributional analysis that will ultimately give greater weight to those groups’ interests. The gamble that Farber and fellow advocates for distributional analysis are making is that the use of lower VSLs for seniors and the use of lower VSLs for disadvantaged minorities will elicit dramatically different reactions.

Although the two cases are distinguishable, the distinctions would seem to suggest that the use of lower VSLs for disadvantaged minorities in the distributional context would be more—not less—problematic from a public perception perspective. In the senior death discount case, the EPA had an easy response to the allegation that it was placing less weight on seniors’ lives than on younger adults’ lives: it wasn’t doing that. Premature deaths due to particulate matter exposure counted for 60% more in the agency’s analysis if the person in question was over age 65 rather than under. If reporters had bothered to read the relevant agency documents, they would have seen that the “senior death discount” accusation was a “four Pinocchios” claim.61 In the distributional context, by contrast, agencies really would be assigning lower average VSLs to African Americans than to non-Hispanic whites when analyzing subgroup-specific effects. Realizing that these lower VSLs would be in service of ensuring that regulations don’t impose disparate impacts on disadvantaged minorities would require a degree of sophistication far beyond what we saw in the senior death discount debate.

Moreover, the United States’ history of racial discrimination heightens the expressive stakes of race-differential VSLs. While the United States has a long history of age discrimination as well as racial discrimination,62 only one of these two forms of discrimination constitutes “America’s original sin.”63 We did not maintain a system of age-based slavery for two-and-a-half centuries, we did not lynch people because of their age, and we did not force older people to ride at the back of the bus (unless they were both older and darker-skinned). Perhaps most significantly, our Constitution never counted elderly people as being worth three-fifths as much as younger adults for purposes of apportioning representatives and direct taxes. The United States’ ugly record on race makes the pursuit of racial justice through cost–benefit analysis all the more urgent but also all the more fraught. Consider that the use of income-adjusted VSLs with an income elasticity of 1 would result in an average VSL for African Americans that is 62% of the VSL for non-Hispanic whites. It does not require hypersensitivity to historical resonance for one to recoil at the idea of assigning a value to African American lives that is roughly three-fifths the value for whites.

Importantly, the concern about using different average VSLs for different racial and ethnic groups is not simply a public relations worry. As I have argued elsewhere in the context of income-adjusted VSLs, “it is a bad thing if millions of Americans think that the federal government values their interests less than the interests of other, richer Americans—and bad for reasons beyond the fact that agency officials may endure a few difficult news cycles.”64 Replace “richer” with “whiter” and the claim becomes even stronger. It is bad because faith in government may decline—and individuals may be discouraged from participating in civic activities—if they think that their government literally values their lives less. And it is bad because disrespect—whether intended or not—imposes its own distinct harms on the individuals who experience it. Ben Eidelson wrote of the senior death discount episode, “[T]he suggestion that some people’s lives were less worth saving was understandably heard to say that the people themselves were worth less.”65 And if it was understandable there (where it was straightforwardly refutable by facts), it is all the more understandable here (where refutation would require many additional analytical steps).

Summing up so far: the equality–equity dilemma in cost–benefit analysis appears to be a genuine dilemma. Maintaining equal-dollar VSLs in distributional analysis would produce results that do not necessarily benefit—and may in fact harm—members of disadvantaged minority groups, but the abandonment of equal-dollar VSLs raises serious concerns that go well beyond “bad PR.” The challenge for distributional analysis is how to account, in a responsible way, for the fact that willingness to pay for fatality risk reduction varies by income without inadvertently (though predictably) conveying a message to lower-income groups and disadvantaged minorities that their lives are valued less than the lives of their fellow citizens.

How should regulatory cost–benefit analysis respond to the equality–equity dilemma? This section sketches out four possible approaches: one that makes VSL equality the priority, a second that gives up on the goal of using cost–benefit analysis to advance equity, a third that seeks to smooth over the dilemma through arithmetic acrobatics, and a fourth that seeks to enlist trusted voices in validating distributional methodologies.

First, and least attractively, regulators could charge full steam ahead on distributional analysis while maintaining equal-dollar VSLs across income, racial, and ethnic groups. By now, the problem with this approach should be clear: regulators would be calculating costs and benefits by subgroup using VSLs that—in the case of African Americans—are roughly 1.5 times the average willingness to pay for fatality risk reduction that members of that group would rationally have, assuming logarithmic utility functions (1.3 times for Latinos). We would, in effect, be congratulating ourselves for advancing racial equity through regulations that in many cases may leave African Americans and Latinos worse off in the aggregate. This approach would not just be haphazard—it would amount to Enron-style accounting with respect to real historical debts toward racial and ethnic minorities. I see nothing to recommend this approach, and I know of no one who advocates it.

Second, upon confronting the equality–equity dilemma, policy makers could give up hope of incorporating racial justice into cost–benefit analysis—at least for rules that reduce fatality risk (which is to say, most high-dollar-cost federal rules). This would not be an entirely unreasonable reaction, even for policy makers who are deeply committed to racial justice. In many cases, data on the distribution of benefits and costs will be too sparse for agencies to say with any confidence whether a regulation benefits or burdens disadvantaged minorities on net. And requiring agencies to assess distributional effects of proposed rules would add an extra step in the regulatory process—a step that would potentially slow down the promulgation of lifesaving policies.66 On top of that, the use of disparate-impact analysis in regulatory decision-making could expose regulations to legal challenges—for example, on grounds that the relevant statute does not authorize the agency to consider distributional consequences. As Farber notes, some broadly worded statutes seem to leave room for regulators to consider distributional effects along racial and socioeconomic dimensions,67 but in other cases, the argument that the agency has authority to consider distributional effects under the relevant statute “may be too much of a stretch.”68 Regulators could conclude—quite rationally—that the uncertain distributional payoffs of disparate-impact analysis do not justify slowing down the regulatory process and placing lifesaving rules in potential legal jeopardy, especially considering the additional risk of expressive harms if disparate-impact analysis abandons equal-dollar VSLs.

Moreover, even if agencies decline to consider racial equity when crafting lifesaving regulations, those same agencies still can seek to advance racial justice in a myriad of other ways. For example, the EPA could continue to make disadvantaged communities top priorities for project funding under its quarter-century-old Environmental Workforce Development and Job Training Program.69 The Department of Transportation could use its discretionary authority to channel infrastructure investments—to the extent permitted by the relevant statutes—toward transit projects in underserved communities.70 Agencies could continue to review and update their procurement policies to ensure that minority-owned businesses can compete successfully for federal contracts. In short, while lifesaving regulations represent the lion’s share of high-dollar-cost federal agency rules, rulemaking is itself just one function of the administrative state. Agencies that face up to the equality–equity dilemma in rulemaking may decide—quite understandably—to focus their equity-promotion efforts on non-rulemaking areas.

Yet I expect that many readers will not be ready to accept this resigned conclusion. The very phenomena that give rise to the equality–equity dilemma—the stark differences in income and risk exposure across racial and ethnic lines—cry out for a robust policy response that doesn’t leave any available tools on the table. In line with this view, President Biden committed his administration on day one to a “whole-of-government equity agenda,”71 and a whole-of-government effort would necessarily include regulation as a component. At the very least, we should consider more creative responses to the equality–equity dilemma before giving up on the goal of advancing racial equity in the risk-regulation domain.

Accordingly, a third approach to the equality–equity dilemma deserves attention and reflection. This third approach would seek to modify the arithmetic terms of analysis to make the use of differential VSLs less salient. The Indian economist E. Somanathan has suggested one method for accomplishing that goal. In Somanathan’s proposal, “[l]ives, rather than money, are used as the unit of account.”72 Everyone’s life could be valued at one life-unit, but the ratio between life-units and dollars could differ by income. For example, say that the median African American worker’s income is two-thirds the population median, the population-median VSL is $12 million, and the income elasticity of the VSL is 1. One dollar would be worth 1/12 million life-units for the median U.S. worker and 1/8 million life-units for the median African American worker. By valuing different people’s dollars differently in life-unit terms, Somanathan’s approach sidesteps the need to value different people’s lives differently in dollar terms.73

The life-unit approach could be used as a complement to or a substitute for standard cost–benefit analysis with equal-dollar VSLs. If it were used as a complement, regulators would first compute population-wide costs and benefits as under the status quo and then analyze effects on each subgroup in life-unit terms. The results of the subgroup analyses would be directionally the same as if regulators had used income-adjusted VSLs: any policy that produces a net benefit for a subgroup in dollar terms also would produce a net benefit for that subgroup in life-unit terms. But regulators never would have to assign different dollar values to different people’s lives. Alternatively, the life-unit approach could replace standard cost–benefit analysis altogether: rather than evaluating policies based on whether they generate net benefits in dollar terms, regulators would evaluate policies based on whether they generate net life-unit gains. In this iteration, life-unit analysis would be a form of equity weighting (since pecuniary costs and benefits for lower-income individuals and groups would count for more in the total tally).74

The life-unit approach has the virtue of being clever. But is it too clever by half? For one thing, expressing costs and benefits in unfamiliar life-unit terms would undermine an oft-cited advantage of cost–benefit analysis: transparency.75 The current practice of cost–benefit analysis, which displays results in terms of dollars, arguably allows laypeople to better understand and critique regulatory choices. Replacing dollars with life-units would render the results of cost–benefit analysis significantly less legible to nonexperts.

For another, the life-unit approach would not entirely inoculate distributional analysis against the charge that regulators are assigning lower VSLs to disadvantaged minorities than to non-Hispanic whites. Whenever an agency rule relied on a distributional analysis that used different life-unit-to-dollar ratios for different groups, opponents of the rule still would have an incentive to point out that, once one cuts through the fractions, the life-unit approach has the effect of assigning lower-dollar VSLs to members of lower-income groups. And they would not be wrong. By avoiding any explicit statement that the VSL is lower for lower-income groups, agencies might leave themselves less vulnerable to “death discount” charges, but they would not be entirely invulnerable.

For that reason, the life-unit approach—if pursued—should be pursued in tandem with a fourth approach to the equality–equity dilemma: enlisting trusted voices to validate distributional methodologies. Before an agency uses income-adjusted VSLs in distributional analysis—either explicitly or through the conceit of life-units—it should seek the support in advance of leaders who enjoy credibility among members of the groups to whom lower VSLs will be assigned. When opponents of an agency rule opportunistically and inevitably level the “death discount” charge, those leaders should be prepared to counter the opponents’ narrative. They should be prepared to explain—in language far more straightforward than this comment’s academic prose—that the use of income-adjusted VSLs doesn’t devalue members of disadvantaged groups but rather advances those groups’ interests.

Who exactly those trusted leaders might be will vary based on the relevant regulations and the affected groups. Elected officials outside the executive branch—for example, senators and congressmembers from disadvantaged minority groups—seem like natural candidates, but the pantheon might also include clergy members, labor union leaders, heads of well-respected civil rights organizations, and prominent advocates within the environmental justice movement. To obtain support, agencies will likely need to reach out early on and integrate potential validators into the regulatory decision-making process. And, of course, racial and ethnic groups are not political monoliths: not all members of a given group will place their trust in any given validator. However, “death discount” charges are much less likely to scar if they encounter immediate and informed resistance from recognized and respected voices.

The analysis here is admittedly speculative. We have no data that demonstrates how income-adjusted VSLs will be received by the public when those adjustments are submerged in opaque arithmetic and/or defended by trusted voices—and the reason we have no data is that no one has tried these approaches. But it is even more speculative, to the point of being wishful thinking, to believe that public acceptance of differential VSLs will come easily. If there is a lesson to be learned from the senior death discount experience, it is that the use of different VSLs for different groups presents challenges that will require careful planning, creativity, and coalition building.

The equality–equity dilemma in cost–benefit analysis warrants attention in its own right because it presents a first-order challenge to efforts to incorporate racial and economic justice into regulatory policy making. But it also merits focus because of what it can potentially teach us about the broader enterprise of cost–benefit analysis, which now suffuses the regulatory state and supplies the justificatory language for life-and-death decisions.

First, the equality–equity dilemma highlights the reality that regulatory cost–benefit analysis operates, if not always in the public eye, at least in the public’s peripheral vision. Occasionally, agencies’ methodological choices leap from the fine print of technical documents into the public’s consciousness. A recent example involved an EPA proposal in late 2022 to impose new and more stringent standards on methane emissions from crude oil and natural gas facilities.76 Buried on page 129 of a technical supplement to the proposal was the agency’s explanation of its module for monetizing the mortality benefits of a reduction in greenhouse gases.77 According to the agency, “[v]aluation of mortality risk changes outside the U.S. is based on an extrapolation of the EPA value that equalizes willingness-to-pay as a percentage of per capita income across all countries (i.e., using an assumed income elasticity of 1).”78

Commentators quickly picked up on what those words meant: for purposes of the methane rule, EPA was valuing foreigners’ lives in proportion to foreigners’ incomes. Thus, as Vox’s Dylan Matthews adroitly observed,

a Canadian life saved is worth over 16 times as much as a Haitian life saved in the EPA’s calculus. That’s because the EPA has chosen to weigh the mortality costs of climate change in proportion to per capita income of the country where someone dies, and Canada’s GDP per capita is more than 16 times that of Haiti. We can keep going. A Qatari life is worth 118 Burundian lives—a Qatari life is worth more than an American life, in fact. A German life is worth 12 Cambodian lives. An Australian life is worth four Indonesian lives. A Russian life is worth two Ukrainian lives. All of these judgments are implicit in the way the EPA is calculating the costs of climate change.79

Importantly, Matthews was careful to stress that these controversial judgments are “implicit” in EPA’s analysis, which never mentioned Qataris, Burundians, or any other specific foreign nationality. And he was right that the EPA’s analysis implied vastly different weights on the lives of individuals in different countries, even though the EPA never explicitly said as much. The story soon hit the NPR airwaves,80 though it has not become the debacle for the agency that the senior death discount was. Perhaps that is because differential VSLs for foreigners don’t elicit the same negative reaction as differential VSLs for Americans; perhaps it is because the Biden EPA enjoys more goodwill than the Bush administration with the environmental groups that seeded the “senior death discount” narrative twenty years ago.81 In any event, the episode is another reminder that what happens in cost–benefit analysis doesn’t always stay in cost–benefit analysis: agencies should be prepared for the technical details of their regulatory assessments to reach nontechnical audiences, sometimes in a transmogrified form.

Second, the equality–equity dilemma underscores the need for agencies to consider—as part of a comprehensive assessment of regulatory costs and benefits—the potential discursive harms that flow from their own articulation of their methodological choices. This, again, is more than a matter of political expedience or bureaucratic self-preservation: accounting for all the costs and benefits of a regulatory proposal requires an agency to consider the consequences of potentially sending a message to some individuals that their lives are worth less. And this is doubly true for distributional analysis, where the discursive harms of differential VSLs—if not carefully managed—will fall disproportionately on members of already disadvantaged groups.

Finally, reflecting on the equality–equity dilemma offers us a richer perspective on cost–benefit analysis’s institutional dimensions. Over the last quarter century, scholars have come to understand cost–benefit analysis as a mechanism that allows the president and his advisers to monitor agencies across the executive branch. Regulation involves trade-offs, and the discipline of cost–benefit analysis makes those trade-offs transparent to White House officials.82 As Jonathan Masur and Eric Posner put it, “quantification forces regulators to put their decisionmaking into a format that can be evaluated by generalist superiors.”83 Scholars have argued that cost–benefit analysis can and should play a parallel function vis-à-vis Congress and the courts, enabling lawmakers and judges to comprehend and critique choices made by expert agencies.84

President Biden’s day-one memorandum can be viewed through this institutional lens: distributional analysis is being used as a technique of presidential administration that seeks to align agency action with the White House’s high-level racial justice objectives. And more generally, the institutionalist perspective has contributed hugely to our understanding of cost–benefit analysis across the regulatory state, highlighting the fact that cost–benefit analysis functions as a management tool as much as a normative decision-making framework. But viewing cost–benefit analysis only in intra-executive or interbranch terms would leave out a critical element of the context in which cost–benefit analysis operates. Cost–benefit analysis renders regulatory decision-making legible not only to actors inside the government but also to outsiders. The equality–equity dilemma arises precisely because the language that regulators use to communicate their decisions to other actors inside government also conveys messages—not always intended—to the broader public.

The equality–equity dilemma thus allows us to see, in stark terms, the opportunities and constraints generated by cost–benefit analysis’s multiple audiences. That cost–benefit analysis must address multiple audiences at once is both a virtue and a vulnerability. It is a virtue insofar as transparency is a virtue: cost–benefit analysis enables citizens to see, in clear terms, how regulators are navigating life-and-death choices that affect us all. It is a vulnerability insofar as it gives rise to the risk that—as in the “senior death discount” case—quantitative inputs may be construed or misconstrued as devaluing certain individuals and groups. In the end, the fact that agencies must simulcast to these multiple audiences may be a net asset or a net liability for the “cost–benefit state.”85 Either way, it is a stubborn reality with which regulators—if they are to use cost–benefit analysis of lifesaving rules as a tool to advance racial justice—must ultimately reckon.

1 

Modernizing Regulatory Review: Memorandum for the Heads of Executive Departments and Agencies, 86 Fed. Reg. 7223 (Jan. 20, 2021), https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefing-room/presidential-actions/2021/01/20/modernizing-regulatory-review.

2 

See Richard L. Revesz & Burçin Ünel, Just Regulation: Improving Distributional Analysis in Agency Rulemaking, Ecology L. Q. (forthcoming), N.Y.U. Sch. L. Pub. L. Research Paper No. 23-26 (manuscript at 4), https://ssrn.com/abstract=4314142.

3 

See, e.g., Archon Fung et al., Democratizing the Federal Regulatory Process: A Blueprint to Strengthen Equity, Dignity, and Civic Engagement Through Executive Branch Action (Harv. Kennedy Sch., HKS Faculty Research Working Paper Series RWP21-025, Oct. 2021); John D. Graham, Incorporating Environmental Justice into Benefit–Cost Analysis of Federal Rulemakings, 25 Rich. Pub. Int. L. Rev. 149 (2022); Thomas J. Kniesner & W. Kip Viscusi, Promoting Equity Through Equitable Risk Tradeoffs (ISA Inst. for Labor Econ., IZA DP No. 15771, Nov. 2022), https://ssrn.com/abstract=4294396; Zachary Liscow, Redistribution for Realists, 107 Iowa L. Rev. 495 (2022); Robert W. Hahn, Equity in Cost Benefit Analysis, 372 Science 439 (2021); Richard L. Revesz, Air Pollution and Environmental Justice, 49 Ecology L. Q. 187 (2022); Richard L. Revesz & Samantha Yi, Distributional Consequences and Regulatory Analysis, 52 Envt L. 53 (2022); Amy Sinden, All the Tools in the Toolbox: A Plea for Flexibility and Open Minds in Assessing the Costs and Benefits of Climate Rules, 39 Yale J. on Reg. 908 (2022); Vanessa Zboreak, Regulatory Reparations, 14 Elon L. Rev. 215 (2022).

4 

Daniel A. Farber, Inequality and Regulation: Designing Rules to Address Race, Poverty, and Environmental Justice, 3 Am. J. L. & Equal. 2, 28 (2023), https://doi.org/10.1162/ajle_a_00048.

5 

Id. at 4.

6 

Id. at 6. Farber thus breaks from authors such as Cass Sunstein, who has written that “the use of a uniform VSL is unacceptably obtuse,” and from other defenders of equal-dollar VSLs (myself included) who believe that current regulatory practice can be defended on grounds of public perception and administrative-cost minimization but not on the basis of ethical first principles. See Cass R. Sunstein, Valuing Life: A Plea for Disaggregation, 54 Duke L.J. 385, 445 (2004); Daniel Hemel, Regulation and Redistribution with Lives in the Balance, 89 U. Chi. L. Rev. 649, 710–13 (2022).

7 

Farber, supra note 4, at 39.

8 

Federal Actions to Address Environmental Justice in Minority Populations and Low-Income Populations, Executive Order 12898, 50 Fed. Reg. 7629 (1994); see David M. Konisky, Introduction, in Failed Promises: Evaluating the Federal Governments Response to Environmental Justice 1, 6 (2015) (“[T]he overall conclusion is that the federal government has failed to live up to most of the promises articulated in EO 12898.”).

9 

Farber, supra note 4, at 39–42.

10 

See Hemel, supra note 6, at 710–13.

11 

Farber, supra note 4, at 24.

12 

See Martha Minow, Equality vs. Equity, 1 Am. J. L. & Equal. 167, 169 (2021).

13 

David A. Weisbach, Review of Daniel Farber, Inequality and Regulation: Designing Rules to Address Race, Poverty, and Environmental Harm, 3 Am. J. L. & Equal. 150, 164 (2023).

14 

See id.

15 

Amartya Sen, Equality of What?, The Tanner Lectures on Human Values (Stanford Univ., May 22, 1979), https://tannerlectures.utah.edu/_resources/documents/a-to-z/s/sen80.pdf.

16 

Cass R. Sunstein, Some Costs & Benefits of Cost–Benefit Analysis, 150 Daedalus 208, 216 (2021).

17 

See infra notes 72–75 and accompanying text.

18 

See Jonathan Colmer, What Is the Meaning of (Statistical) Life? Benefit–Cost Analysis in the Time of COVID-19, 36 Oxford Rev. Econ. Poly S56, S57 (2020).

19 

EPA, Off. Air and Radiation, The Benefits and Costs of the Clean Air Act from 1990 to 2020, Final Report – Rev. A 7-3 (Apr. 2011).

20 

Out of twenty-four federal rules adopted between 2001 and 2018 with annual costs exceeding $1 billion, ten directly address air pollution and seven deal with vehicle safety. Three more of the twenty-four are vehicle fuel economy standards, which implicate both air pollution and vehicle safety. See Hemel, supra note 6, at 666–68 tbl.1.

21 

While theoretically there could be a divergence between the willingness to pay for a mortality risk reduction and the willingness to accept a mortality risk increase, Thomas Kniesner, Kip Viscusi, and James Ziliak found that empirically these numbers converge. Specifically, the authors compared workers who move from higher-risk to lower-risk jobs (who are, in effect, “paying” for mortality risk reduction through lower wages) and workers who move from lower-risk to higher-risk jobs (i.e., who are, in effect, “accepting” a mortality risk increase in exchange for higher wages). They find “no economic or statistically significant difference between willingness to accept and willingness to pay.” Thomas J. Kniesner et al., Willingness to Accept Equals Willingness to Pay for Labor Market Estimates of the Value of a Statistical Life, 48 J. Risk & Uncertainty 187, 188 (2014).

22 

Daniel Hemel & Jonathan Masur, Valuing Future Lives 2 n.2 (2023) (unpublished manuscript) (on file with author) (collecting agency estimates).

23 

See id. at 13–16 (compiling empirical estimates).

24 

See Hemel, supra note 6, at 657.

25 

The Environmental Protection Agency, which continues to use a value of 0.49 in the domestic context, is the one exception. See Hemel & Masur, supra note 6, at 34.

26 

Some studies estimate the income elasticity of the VSL to be substantially higher than 1. For example, applying a technique known as quantile regression to data from the 1993 through 2001 waves of the Panel Study of Income Dynamics, Thomas Kniesner, Kip Viscusi, and James Ziliak estimated the income elasticity of the VSL for U.S. workers to be 1.44. Thomas J. Kniesner et al., Policy Relevant Heterogeneity in the Value of Statistical Life: New Evidence from Panel Data Quantile Regressions, 40 J. Risk & Uncertainty 15, 28 (2010). Combining U.S. census microdata and Bureau of Labor Statistics fatality data from 1940 to 1980, Dora Costa and Matthew Kahn estimated the income elasticity of the VSL to be 1.5 to 1.7. See Dora L. Costa & Matthew E. Kahn, Changes in the Value of Life, 1940–1980, 29 J. Risk & Uncertainty 159, 172–73 (2004). As Louis Kaplow observed, if the utility of income is the natural logarithm of income, then we should expect the income elasticity of the VSL to be somewhat above 1. An income elasticity of 1 implies that rich and poor people derive the same utility from their lives, but presumably it’s more pleasant to be alive when rich. See Louis Kaplow, The Value of a Statistical Life and the Coefficient of Relative Risk Aversion, 31 J. Risk & Uncertainty 23, 24–25 (2005).

27 

See Departmental Guidance on Valuation of a Statistical Life in Economic Analysis, U.S. Dept of Transp., (Mar. 23, 2021), https://www.transportation.gov/office-policy/transportation-policy/revised-departmental-guidance-on-valuation-of-a-statistical-life-in-economic-analysis.

28 

The analysis here uses household income for illustrative purposes, though a more precise estimate of average VSLs across racial and ethnic groups would incorporate several adjustments. The census measure of household income includes most transfer payments (e.g., Social Security, Supplemental Security Income, public assistance, and unemployment and workers’ compensation), but it does not subtract income taxes. See U.S. Census Bureau, Current Population Survey: 2022 Annual Social and Economic (ASEC) Supplement 7-3 (2022), https://www2.census.gov/programs-surveys/cps/techdocs/cpsmar22.pdf. The census measure also excludes capital gains—both realized and unrealized—as well as the annuitized value of nonfinancial wealth. See id. These factors push in opposite directions: the failure to subtract taxes enlarges the difference in after-tax-and-transfer incomes between non-Hispanic whites and African Americans, while the failure to include capital gains and the annuitized value of nonfinancial wealth narrows the gap. In theory, the use of household income without adjustment for household size also could affect estimates, but census data indicates that average household size is the same across both groups (2.50 people per household). See America’s Families and Living Arrangements: 2016, tbl.AVG1. Average Number of People per Household, by Race and Hispanic Origin, Marital Status, Age, and Education of Householder: 2016, U.S. Census Bureau (Nov. 2016), https://www2.census.gov/programs-surveys/demo/tables/families/2016/cps-2016/tabavg1.xls.

29 

See W. Kip Viscusi, Racial Differences in Labor Market Values of a Statistical Life, 27 J. Risk & Uncertainty 239, 250 tbl.4, 252 tbl.5 (2003).

30 

See id. at 254–55.

31 

Id. at 254. Importantly, Viscusi’s regression estimates control for education and occupational group but not for income or wealth. See id. at 250 tbl.4. For technical reasons, wage-risk studies cannot effectively control for income directly because wage and income are highly collinear and wage is the outcome variable in these studies. See Hemel & Masur, supra note 22, at 14. Part of the observed difference between white and African American workers’ VSLs in Viscusi’s estimates thus may be attributable to income effects. However, in Viscusi’s study, the percentage difference in VSLs is much larger than the percentage difference in wages: white workers have VSLs that are 44% higher than African American workers’ in Viscusi’s non-logged estimate, while their weekly wages are 22% higher. See Viscusi, supra note 29, at 252 tbl.5. For the entire VSL gap to be explained by income effects, the income elasticity of the VSL would need to be around 2 (or potentially higher, given that some of the variation in incomes may be captured already by the education and occupation-group controls). An income elasticity of 2 is higher than most—though not all—empirical estimates of the income elasticity of the VSL. See Hemel & Masur, supra note 22, at 14–16.

32 

James K. Hammitt & Kevin Haninger, Valuing Fatal Risks to Children and Adults: Effects of Disease, Latency, and Risk Aversion, 40 J. Risk & Uncertainty 57, 73 tbl.3, 78 tbl.5 (2010).

33 

See John Loomis, What’s to Know About Hypothetical Bias in Stated Preference Valuation Studies?, 25 J. Econ. Survs. 363 (2011).

34 

U.S. Dept of Transp., 2010 Status of the Nations Highways, Bridges, and Transit: Conditions & Performance—Report to Congress 1–4 tbl.1-2 (2010), https://www.fhwa.dot.gov/policy/2010cpr/pdfs/cp2010.pdf.

35 

See Julie Bennett & YiLi Chien, The Large Gap in Stock Market Participation Between Black and White Households, 7 Economic Synopses (Mar. 28, 2022), https://doi.org/10.20955/es.2022.7.

36 

See Labor Force Statistics from the Current Population Survey—Household Data—Annual Averages—18. Employed Persons by Detailed Industry, Sex, Race, and Hispanic or Latino Ethnicity, U.S. Bureau of Lab. Stat. (Jan. 25, 2023), https://www.bls.gov/cps/cpsaat18.htm.

37 

In 2021, African Americans constituted 18.6% of nonelderly Medicaid beneficiaries, and Hispanics constituted 29.2%. See Distribution of the Nonelderly with Medicaid by Race/Ethnicity—Timeframe: 2021, Kaiser Fam. Found., https://www.kff.org/medicaid/state-indicator/medicaid-distribution-nonelderly-by-raceethnicity (last visited Feb. 12, 2023).

38 

In a thoughtful recent essay, Cass Sunstein wrote that “[i]n the case of subsidies, the use of a VSL that reflects the population average, or even the number for the top quartile, would be very much in the interest of poor people” but then added the “major qualification” that money “must come from somewhere” and “we cannot rule out the possibility that its use here will mean it will be unavailable for some other program or initiative from which poor people would benefit more.” Cass R. Sunstein, Inequality and the Value of a Statistical Life 1–2, 4 (Oct. 2, 2022), https://ssrn.com/abstract=4236366. As I see it, the qualification swallows the initial statement. Even when lawmakers explicitly say that they will pay for risk-reduction projects out of tax revenues, the choice to pursue one particular project may come at the expense of other projects that would benefit lower-income groups.

39 

See Hemel, supra note 6, at 690–700.

40 

See Departmental Guidance on Valuation of a Statistical Life in Economic Analysis, U.S. Dept of Transp. (Mar. 23, 2021), https://www.transportation.gov/office-policy/transportation-policy/revised-departmental-guidance-on-valuation-of-a-statistical-life-in-economic-analysis.

41 

For example, if the costs of vehicle safety standards were proportionate to vehicle ownership, a switch from income-adjusted VSLs to population-average VSLs would potentially generate net benefits for African Americans and net costs for non-Hispanic whites.

42 

See Farber, supra note 4, at 28.

43 

David Weisbach makes this same point in his comment elsewhere in this issue. See Weisbach, supra note 13. He concludes that while it is possible that “using equal VSLs helps the poor because of how the incidence of the costs and benefits shakes out,” there is “no reason to believe that this is the case.” See id. at 162.

44 

Even if we had rich data on the distribution of costs and benefits for adopted regulations, we still wouldn’t know whether the use of population-average VSLs benefits or burdens lower-income groups because regulatory decisions are endogenous to the relevant decision rule. Thus, to know whether lower-income groups benefit from the use of population-average VSLs, we would need to observe the counterfactual in which agencies apply income-adjusted VSLs and determine whether the regulations adopted in the counterfactual leave lower-income groups better off or worse off than under the status quo.

45 

I thank my colleague Liam Murphy for this observation.

46 

As noted above, these three categories comprise twenty of the twenty-four federal regulations with more than $1 billion in annual costs adopted between 2001 and 2018. See Hemel, supra note 6, at 666–68 tbl.1; supra note 20.

47 

See 42 U.S.C. § 7409.

48 

As Table 1 notes, the National Safety Council reports 3,281 deaths of African American non-Hispanic passenger vehicle occupants and 12,480 deaths of white non-Hispanic passenger vehicle occupants in 2019. 3,281/12,480 ≈ 0.263.

49 

See, e.g., Kylie Conrad & John D. Graham, The Benefits and Costs of Automotive Regulations for Low-Income Americans, 12 J. Benefit-Cost Anal. 518, 527 (2021) (noting that for purposes of distributional analysis, “assuming a uniform VSL value for all income groups is not informative”).

50 

Farber, supra note 4, at 24.

51 

Kniesner & Viscusi, supra note 3, at 20; see also W. Kip Viscusi, The Benefits of Mortality Risk Reduction: Happiness Surveys vs. the Value of a Statistical Life, 62 Duke L.J. 1735, 1742 (2013) (“By using a uniform VSL across different populations, agencies engage in an implicit form of income redistribution, as benefits to the poor receive a greater weight than is justified by their VSL and benefits to the rich are undervalued.”).

52 

See Kniesner & Viscusi, supra note 3, at 6. Even that statement arguably fails to capture the extent of the risk that higher VSLs will hurt the worst off. As noted, higher VSLs can lead to the adoption of policies that hurt lower-income groups both when “costs are borne privately” (e.g., when costs of higher vehicle-safety standards are passed through to car buyers and when costs of more stringent air pollution limits are passed through to energy consumers) and when costs are borne publicly (by the government). Again, when higher VSLs push policy makers to adopt more stringent regulations—and those more stringent regulations impose costs on the public sector—lower-income groups potentially bear the brunt, as public-sector costs may come at the expense of social programs that primarily benefit members of lower-income groups.

53 

Farber, supra note 4, at 3; see also Richard L. Revesz & Michael A. Livermore, Retaking Rationality: How Costbenefit Analysis Can Better Protect the Environment and Our Health 14 (2008) (“[T]he value of the benefit typically assigned to life-saving regulations is the same no matter what the target population. … In general, this use of average values has a redistributive effect from richer to poorer.”).

54 

EPA, Technical Addendum: Methodologies for the Benefit Analysis of the Clear Skies Initiative 35–36 (Sept. 2002), https://perma.cc/GH44-7MAK [hereinafter Technical Addendum].

55 

EPA, Regulatory Impact Analysis of the Proposed Reciprocating Internal Combustion Engines NESHAP (Nov. 2002), https://www.epa.gov/sites/default/files/2014-02/documents/riceria_november2002.pdf [hereinafter RICE Regulatory Impact Analysis].

56 

Technical Addendum, supra note 54, at 50; RICE Regulatory Impact Analysis, supra note 55, at 8–23 tbl.8-3.

57 

See Technical Addendum, supra note 54, at 36; RICE Regulatory Impact Analysis, supra note 55, at 8–29.

58 

Press Release, Nat’l Res. Def. Council, Cheapening the Value of Life: The Bush Administration’s Death Discount (Apr. 1, 2003), https://perma.cc/5WZ6-N36C.

59 

John Tierney, Life: The Cost–Benefit Analysis, N.Y. Times (May 18, 2003), https://www.nytimes.com/2003/05/18/weekinreview/life-the-cost-benefit-analysis.html.

60 

See Hemel, supra note 6, at 717; Dennis O’Brien, EPA Finds Life Worth the Same at Age 70, Balt. Sun (May 28, 2003), https://www.baltimoresun.com/news/bs-xpm-2003-05-08-0305080064-story.html.

61 

The reference is to the Washington Post Fact Checker’s rating system, which graded claims for falsity on a zero-to-four-Pinocchios scale before the paper added a new grade—“Bottomless Pinocchios”—specifically for Donald Trump. See Glenn Kessler & Jon Fox, The False Claims That Trump Keeps Repeating, Wash. Post (Jan. 20, 2021), https://www.washingtonpost.com/graphics/politics/fact-checker-most-repeated-disinformation.

62 

For an overview of the history of age discrimination in U.S. constitutional law, see Nina A. Kohn, Rethinking the Constitutionality of Age Discrimination: A Challenge to a Decades-Old Consensus, 44 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 213 (2010).

63 

Cf. Annette Gordon-Reed, America’s Original Sin: Slavery and the Legacy of White Supremacy, Foreign Affs. (Jan./Feb. 2018), https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/united-states/2017-12-12/americas-original-sin.

64 

Hemel, supra note 6, at 715.

65 

Benjamin Eidelson, Comment, Kidney Allocation and the Limits of the Age Discrimination Act, 122 Yale L. J. 1635, 1648 (2013).

66 

See Hemel, supra note 6, at 720–74. In this respect, the concern about distributional analysis runs parallel to Nicholas Bagley’s argument that adding new procedural hurdles along the rulemaking pathway exerts antiregulatory effects. See Nicholas Bagley, The Procedure Fetish, 118 Mich. L. Rev. 345 (2019).

67 

See Farber, supra note 4, at 40.

68 

See id. at 43. For example, the Clean Air Act requires the EPA to set primary national ambient air quality standards (NAAQS) that, “in the judgment of the Administrator,” and “allowing an adequate margin of safety,” are “requisite to protect the public health.” 42 U.S.C. § 7409(b). The Supreme Court has held that this provision “unambiguously bars cost considerations from the NAAQS-setting process.” Whitman v. Am. Trucking Ass’ns, 531 U.S. 457, 471 (2001). As Farber notes, if the EPA can’t consider costs at all, then presumably it can’t consider which racial and ethnic groups bear those costs. See Farber, supra note 4, at 21 n.103. For a closer-to-the-edge example, Farber cites 42 U.S.C. § 7411(a), which requires the EPA to adopt performance standards for new stationary sources that reflect “the best system of emission reduction which … the Administrator determines has been adequately demonstrated.” See Farber, supra note 4, at 43 n.228. Although the EPA would have a plausible argument that the word “best” allows consideration of costs and benefits for disadvantaged groups, Farber expresses doubt that this argument would prevail in court. See Farber, supra note 4, at 43.

69 

See EPA, Transforming Lives and Advancing Economic Opportunity: EPA’s Environmental Workforce Development and Job Training Program 2 (Apr. 2016), https://www.epa.gov/sites/default/files/2016-05/documents/epa_case_studies_final_042116_508_smaller.pdf (noting that from its inception in 1998 to the end of 2015, EPA’s job training program allocated more than $54 million in grants and helped more than 10,200 individuals secure employment in the environmental field). The bipartisan infrastructure law passed in 2021 added $600 million in funding over five years for brownfield-related projects, including job training grants. Infrastructure Investment and Jobs Act, Pub. L. No. 117-58, 135 Stat. 427, 1403 (2021).

70 

As the Department of Transportation noted, the 2021 bipartisan infrastructure law “provides an unprecedented level of competitive grant funding that can directly benefit disadvantaged communities in urban and rural areas”—$196 billion according to the department’s tally. See U.S. Dept of Transp., Equity Action Plan 9 (Jan. 2022), https://www.transportation.gov/sites/dot.gov/files/2022-04/Equity_Action_Plan.pdf.

71 

Exec. Order 13985, 86 Fed. Reg. 7009, 7009 (Jan. 25, 2021).

72 

E. Somanathan, Valuing Lives Equally: Distributional Weights for Welfare Analysis, 90 Econ. Letters 122, 123 (2006).

73 

While this comment was in the publication process, the White House Office of Management and Budget (OMB) released a draft for public review of a revised Circular A-4, the framework document for regulatory cost–benefit analysis. Off. of Mgmt. & Budget, Circular A-4—Draft for Public Review (Apr. 6, 2023), https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-content/uploads/2023/04/DraftCircularA-4.pdf. The draft proposed that agencies incorporate distributional considerations into cost–benefit analysis by assigning greater weight to dollar costs and benefits borne by lower-income groups but assigning equal-dollar VSLs to all. See id. at 65–66. The proposed approach is arithmetically equivalent to the life-unit approach described in the text, except with weighted dollars rather than life units as the relevant yardstick. (The OMB draft also proposed an income elasticity of 1.4 rather than the income elasticity of 1 used for illustrative purposes above. See id. at 65.) By assigning greater weight to dollars in the hands of lower-income individuals but equal-dollar VSLs to all, the approach proposed in the Circular A-4 draft would reflect the reality that willingness to pay for mortality risk reduction is lower for lower-income individuals. With a population-average VSL of $12 million, a regulation that reduced the risk of death by one in 12 million at a cost per person of $1 would be breakeven for the population at large but would be scored as having negative net benefits for lower-income groups. A full analysis of the weighted-dollar approach lies beyond this comment’s scope. The use of weighted dollars for non-mortality costs and benefits along with equal-dollar VSLs comes with many of the same advantages as the life-unit approach and also faces similar challenges.

74 

See Hemel, supra note 6, at 715–16.

75 

See, e.g., Caroline Cecot & Robert W. Hahn, Transparency in Agency Cost–Benefit Analysis, 72 Admin. L. Rev. 157, 164 & n.28 (2020) (stating that CBA “promotes transparency by revealing the likely economic and social impacts of agency decisions to policymakers and interested parties,” and citing nine other sources that advance a similar proposition).

76 

EPA, Standards of Performance for New, Reconstructed, and Modified Sources and Emissions Guidelines for Existing Sources: Oil and Natural Gas Sector Climate Review—Supplemental Notice of Proposed Rulemaking, 87 Fed. Reg. 74,702 (Dec. 26, 2022).

77 

EPA, Report on the Social Cost of Greenhouse Gases: Estimates Incorporating Recent Scientific Advances 129 (external review draft, Sept. 2022), https://www.epa.gov/system/files/documents/2022-11/epa_scghg_report_draft_0.pdf.

78 

Id.

79 

Dylan Matthews, The Tricky Business of Putting a Dollar Value on a Human Life, Vox (Dec. 22, 2022), https://www.vox.com/future-perfect/23449849/social-cost-carbon-value-statistical-life-epa (paragraph break omitted).

80 

Rebecca Hersher, The EPA Is Updating Its Most Important Tool for Cracking Down on Carbon Emissions, NPR (Feb. 4, 2023), https://www.npr.org/2023/02/04/1152080009/the-epa-is-updating-its-most-important-tool-for-cracking-down-on-carbon-emission. In the interests of full disclosure, I spoke with both Matthews and Hersher and am quoted in the Vox article and the NPR segment. Both reporters, in my view, handled the issue of differential VSLs with sensitivity and sophistication.

81 

Press Release, Nat’l Res. Def. Council, Demand Strong Safeguards on Climate-Busting Methane (Jan. 8, 2023), https://action.nrdc.org/letter/1346-epa-methane-010423 (stating that EPA’s proposal “improves upon many of the standards in the original proposal released by EPA in 2021,” though also adding that “it does not go far enough”).

82 

For classic statements of this view, see Elena Kagan, Presidential Administration, 114 Harv. L. Rev. 2245, 2278–79 (2001); Eric A. Posner, Controlling Agencies with Cost–Benefit Analysis: A Positive Political Theory Perspective, 68 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1137, 1140 (2001).

83 

Jonathan S. Masur & Eric A. Posner, Cost–Benefit Analysis and the Judicial Role, 85 U. Chi. L. Rev. 935, 940 (2018).

84 

On cost–benefit analysis and Congress, see Caroline Cecot, Congress and Cost–Benefit Analysis, 73 Admin. L. Rev. 787 (2021). On cost–benefit analysis and the courts, see Masur & Posner, supra note 83; Cass R. Sunstein, Cost–Benefit Analysis and Arbitrariness Review, 41 Harv. Envt L. Rev. 1 (2017).

85 

Cf. Cass R. Sunstein, Congress, Constitutional Moments, and the Cost–Benefit State, 48 Stan. L. Rev. 247, 249 (1996).

Author notes

*

Professor of Law, New York University School of Law. For helpful comments, the author thanks Ryan Bubb, Kevin Davis, David Elkins, Dan Farber, Brittany Farr, Barry Friedman, Daniel Hulsebosch, Marcel Kahan, David Kamin, Daryl Levinson, Troy McKenzie, Liam Murphy, Michael Ohlrogge, Rick Pildes, Noah Rosenblum, Catherine Sharkey, Richard Stewart, Burçin Ünel, Kip Viscusi, Katrina Wyman, participants in the N.Y.U. School of Law Faculty Workshop, and the editors of the American Journal of Law and Equality.

This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License, which permits you to copy and redistribute in any medium or format, for non-commercial use only, provided that the original work is not remixed, transformed, or built upon, and that appropriate credit to the original source is given. For a full description of the license, please visit https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/legalcode.