Regulatory review’s primary tool is economic: cost–benefit analysis. But regulation’s consequences are not just economic; they are also political. In this article, I offer a new approach to regulatory review, one with politics at its core. I show why politics matters for regulation and how policy makers can rigorously assess their decisions’ political implications over time.

If regulators should think about politics, what values should guide them? To answer this question, I focus on an especially important subset of policy challenges, which I call “structural risks.” These are systemic problems that worsen over time, such as climate change. Structural risks bring into stark relief the importance of politics for regulatory review: they affect the political capacities of future generations, are exceptionally complex, and require durable political coalitions to be managed.

I argue that there are strong reasons, both principled and pragmatic, to regulate these risks democratically—that is, in ways that respect and reinforce citizens’ freedom and equality. Structural-risk regulation requires defining goals across ecological, economic, and other large-scale systems. Administrators’ mandate to choose these goals demands democratic legitimation. And their policies will be less effective without the social trust that democracy can best provide.

I then offer concrete suggestions for democratizing regulation. Most importantly, I argue that structural-risk regulation should be “democratically durable.” Drawing on emerging social-science research, I contend that regulators should consider not just cumulative costs and benefits but also the policy feedbacks of proposed rules. Effective regulation requires attending to how new policies create new politics. Moreover, regulators should assess these consequences in explicitly democratic terms. The result would be an administrative state better able to confront today’s systemic challenges—and with a stronger democratic claim to doing so.

How should regulators assess the long-term consequences of their policy choices? With challenges including climate change, pandemic preparedness, and artificial intelligence all looming, regulating with a view toward the future seems more important than ever. Yet the prevailing approaches to this problem are incomplete.1 Scholars have long debated how much to discount future interests when projecting policies’ cumulative costs and benefits (and related questions).2 Some have further argued that cost–benefit analysis itself can misrepresent our moral relations to future generations.3 Though these debates have been illuminating, they have often neglected regulation’s distinctively political significance. When administrators promulgate climate regulations, for example, their choices both reflect and shape the distribution of political power. Commentators have not wholly missed these dynamics; all recognize that regulatory choices require political judgment. But while the Office of Information and Regulatory Affairs (OIRA) has institutionalized the economic analysis of proposed rules, no comparable infrastructure exists for their political analysis. Nor have scholars much envisaged it.4

There have been some signs of change. Immediately upon taking office, President Joseph R. Biden announced an initiative to “moderniz[e]” regulatory review.5 President Biden’s memorandum called for new approaches to “environmental stewardship,” to promoting “the interests of future generations,” and to “fully account[ing] for regulatory benefits that are difficult or impossible to quantify.”6 To carry out this agenda, the President appointed to OIRA progressive scholars attentive in their writings to the politics of public policy, including Sharon Block, K. Sabeel Rahman, and (as Administrator) Richard Revesz.7

These developments are promising, but they inevitably have left important matters unaddressed. For example, the memorandum sought reforms to “promote the efficiency, transparency, and inclusiveness of the interagency review process.”8 These three aims might all be understood in democratic terms. Yet they might also appear to sit in tension with one another: transparency might hinder efficiency; efficiency might tell against inclusiveness; and even inclusiveness might be served by diminished transparency. So understood, the “Modernizing Regulatory Review” memorandum suggests some expanded role for democracy in regulation while leaving substantial questions unresolved about what, exactly, that role should be.9

In this article, I take the Biden memorandum as impetus to sketch a new approach to high-stakes regulation of long-term problems, one with politics at its core. I focus on what I call “structural risks,” exemplified by the climate crisis: systemic problems that tend over time both to increase in magnitude and to become more difficult to redress. Structural risks place special stress upon conceptions of regulatory review that neglect politics. Structural risks invite—indeed, require—present regulators to make decisions that can profoundly affect future generations. Structural-risk regulation also tends to be exceptionally complex. And structural-risk regulation must also be politically stable over the long haul: it is dangerous to promulgate rules one year, only to have them reversed the next.

Considering, then, the central role of politics in regulating structural risks, I argue that there are good reasons, both principled and pragmatic, for structural-risk regulation to reflect and reinforce the core democratic values of citizens’ freedom and equality. For those who value democracy for its own sake, structural-risk regulations are profoundly important. They not only affect important, large-scale systems (including social and political systems) but ideally follow from contestable choices about what those systems should look like over time. Those who value democracy only instrumentally—say, as a means to effectuate good policy—also have especially strong reasons to care about democratic principles here. Failing to treat citizens as free and equal, I argue, is likely to undermine the trust and knowledge necessary to regulate structural risks effectively. Moreover, if regulators neglect the political consequences of their decisions, they are likely to miss important determinants of policy efficacy.

I identify, justify, and elaborate six principles for a “democratic approach” to modernizing regulatory review.10 These principles sweep widely, addressing both the process and the substance of regulation.11 Though they leave room for structured experimentation,12 the six principles support several specific reforms: first, setting systemic policy goals before developing structural-risk regulations; second, attending to new forms of public input, such as assemblies of randomly selected citizens; and third, assessing potential regulations for their long-term political durability by drawing upon social-scientific expertise beyond economic cost–benefit analysis.

The last of these proposed reforms is especially significant. Some legal scholars have certainly recognized policy feedbacks’ importance.13 But to my knowledge, none has yet analyzed in depth how to integrate consideration of those feedbacks into regulatory review writ large. I offer such an account. My discussion of policy feedbacks is grounded in the ideal of “democratic durability” and integrated into a broader vision of the regulatory process. Yet even those who reject this larger vision should want regulatory reviewers to consider policy feedbacks. Politics constrains public policy in ways not easily described as costs or benefits. Too-narrow devotion to the tools of economics risks missing both threats and opportunities for regulation.

***

In the analysis that follows, I take democracy, roughly speaking, to require political institutions that can be justified in terms of the freedom and equality of all citizens. Respecting citizens as equals means respecting their ability to make decisions about how political life should go—that is, their capacity for political judgment.14 This ideal is admittedly ambiguous, not least in its institutional significance. But one natural implication is that government should be equally accountable to all its citizens.15 Whether through prospective consultation, retrospective elections, or reason-giving, making government answerable to citizens’ claims seems essential to manifesting respect for their judgments.

“Democracy” is, of course, a contested concept, and some will dispute my definition.16 Nonetheless, I believe it represents shared ground among many democratic theorists. For example, some ground democracy’s value in individual autonomy.17 Whatever else realizing autonomy might require, it plausibly demands institutions justifiable (in some sense) in terms of respect for citizens’ capacity for judgment. Others ground democracy in an ideal of citizens relating as social equals, without invidious hierarchies.18 This value, too, requires institutional respect of much the same sort. Seeking to remain on common terrain, I take the basic form of the existing administrative state as given and then invoke my stipulated democratic principles to develop recommendations for reform.19

As for my focus on structural risks, that serves two main purposes. First, it offers analytical clarity, which facilitates specification of when and how democracy matters. Some saw President Biden’s memorandum as an opportunity “to fully account for the interests of future generations and … existential risks.”20 “Structural risk” is a single category that can capture much (though not all) of what matters about these pressing challenges.

Second, “structural risk” offers a theoretical test case for my proposed reforms. I show that there are particularly strong reasons to embrace a “democratic approach” to regulating structural risks. Defining systems-level goals before regulating, for example, is advisable in addressing all systemic risks—but it is especially important when those risks exhibit substantial path dependency. Reinforcing democratic values in the process of choosing goals and developing regulations is worthwhile for all “significant regulatory action[s]”21—but particularly for those addressing risks involving profound problems of social coordination. And regulations generally should be politically durable and therefore subject to review for their potential policy feedbacks—but such review is most significant for rules likely to shape significantly the political future.

My approach might also have appeal beyond this context. If my ideas seem plausible in the context of structural risk, that is more reason to investigate their potential elsewhere. And if they do not, the countervailing considerations are likely to reveal more clearly the limits of “democratizing” administrative reforms.

The remainder of this article consists of three parts. Part I further defines and discusses structural risks. Part II lays out procedural and substantive principles for structural-risk regulation. Part III responds to some possible objections to my proposals.22

I define structural risks as having three characteristic features:

  • 1) 

    They threaten greater harm over time; i.e., they exhibit increasing returns with respect to harm.

  • 2) 

    They become costlier to redress over time; i.e., they exhibit increasing returns with respect to cost of redress.

  • 3) 

    They may cause significant and systemic harm.

Two concepts here are especially important: “increasing returns” and “systemic harm.” Increasing-returns processes exist when “the probability of further steps along the same path increases with each move down that path … because the relative benefits of the current activity compared with other possible options increase over time.”23 Systemic harms are those affecting certain “regularly interacting or interdependent group[s] of items forming … unified whole[s].”24 Systemic harms are never wholly localized, but instead affect interlocked processes. Because “systems” may exist at any scale, I limit the definition of “structural risk” to those threatening “significant” harm. Significance here cannot be fully defined in advance: the point is simply to pick out risks important enough that the marginal costs of implementing the reforms I describe below could likely be justified.

Together, the three features identify risks posing especially difficult problems of intertemporal political choice. Consider the climate crisis. Climate change involves greater potential damage as atmospheric greenhouse gases accumulate; its harms become more difficult to redress as new positive-feedback processes begin; and it threatens substantial harm to global economic, social, and ecological systems. By contrast, persistent pollutants, such as polyfluoroalkyl substances (PFAS), may become increasingly difficult to remediate over time, but they generally do not cause escalating harm. And though asteroid collisions threaten systemic harm, they probably do not become costlier to avoid. Decisions affecting the climate today therefore may have huge ramifications for the future, in ways decisions about PFAS or asteroids might not. These ramifications pose a normative problem, insofar as today’s policy makers ought not to leave future persons in bad positions that are difficult to redress. They also pose a motivational problem, insofar as present decision-makers perceive little interest in acting upon that moral obligation (and much pressure to act contrary to it).25

Structural risks pose other distinctive challenges, as well. For one thing, because structural risks threaten systemic harm, they often exhibit nonlinearities. Systems are characteristically interdependent, so what happens in one part of a system does not usually stay there. These interactions can cascade suddenly and unpredictably, sometimes to catastrophic effect. Moreover, because the costs of redress tend to increase over time, it is preferable (all else equal) to mitigate structural risks sooner rather than later. For both these reasons, structural risks should generally be especially high priorities for regulation.

In some cases, it may be unclear whether a given risk is “structural.” For example, much depends upon how “harm” is calculated. Should policy makers choose not to discount future costs and benefits at all, then PFAS discharges might well cause more harm over time, if only because more people could be exposed to the pollutant as the years pass. Similar considerations apply to determining the cost of redress. These ambiguities suggest that almost any risk could, in principle, be characterized as “structural.” In practice, such determinations will be political, in terms of both how and why they are made.26 In general, institutional context is likely to affect the production, consumption, and interpretation of information about risks.27 The same holds for categorizing risks: what might seem path-dependent and systemic from one perspective may seem fluid and localized from another.

For my purposes, however, such fuzziness is not fatal. For many important risks, designating them as “structural” will be uncontroversial. However else one might characterize the risks associated with climate change or pandemics, they are clearly structural in my sense. For harder cases, scholars, politicians, and regulators can reason backward from structural risks’ policy implications. That is, they can ask whether a given problem creates particular problems of intertemporal choice, nonlinearity, and increasing cost of redress. If so, then it may be appropriate to treat that risk as structural, even if it could also be analyzed in other terms.

A. Process Principles

This subpart outlines three normative principles for the process of developing structural-risk regulations. The core theoretical idea is that regulatory procedures should reinforce democracy, for reasons both principled and pragmatic. I offer some concrete suggestions for pursuing this goal, building upon recent work in democratic theory. These recommendations are not intended to be definitive: other procedural schemes may be compatible with the broad structure I propose, and experimenting with these may prove fruitful.

Principle #1: Choices about systems-level goals should generally precede structural-risk regulations.

Regulating systemic risks involves particular epistemic challenges. The characteristics of any particular component of a system depend substantially upon the characteristics of the system as a whole.28 It is therefore generally difficult to aggregate component-level choices to obtain particular systemic goals. For example, whether or not electrifying the automotive sector contributes to overall environmental sustainability depends upon the characteristics of electricity generation, lithium and cobalt mining, and much else. This does not mean marginal progress is impossible without perfect knowledge. But that progress may be inadequate for achieving broader objectives, even in aggregate. And because structural risks, in particular, threaten greater harms over time, they can overwhelm any gains made.

When considering structural risks, policy makers should ideally determine systems-level goals before identifying possible responses.29 Doing so would allow them to choose more effectively among regulatory options. Concretely, this might mean asking the following questions, among others: What characterizes an environmentally sustainable economy? Or a society resilient against pandemics? Of course, these will generate further questions. Consider, for example, the internationally adopted Sustainable Development Goals, which include not only seventeen high-level goals but also a “shared blueprint” with 169 targets.30 In some cases, this process of goal setting and elaboration may seem easy. Net-zero greenhouse-gas emissions, for example, is surely one necessary aspect of environmental sustainability. But some dispute the value of sustainability in the first place, the net-zero ambition, or the appropriate timeline for achieving it. Even where there is broad agreement, some choices may remain difficult, especially those concerning novel risks.

Though goal setting ought generally to precede policy making, this should not foreclose either swift regulatory action or iterative assessment of objectives. In some cases, it may be appropriate to impose even stringent regulations before setting all relevant objectives. For example, some have endorsed an “Anti-Catastrophe Principle,” according to which policy makers should adopt a “maximin” strategy in the face of (1) a potential catastrophe (2) the likelihood of which cannot be assigned a probability, but which (3) rises above some minimal threshold.31 In these cases, the regulatory task may consist more of preserving the status quo than of pursuing systemic change, making goal setting inapposite. In other cases, policy makers may wish to update goals set by their predecessors in light of changing conditions or new information. Setting systems-level goals may therefore be an iterative process, incorporating both new normative judgments from democratic processes and new insights from regulatory science.32

Some generalist administrative body is necessary to lead the goal-setting process; OIRA is the most likely candidate today. Setting systems-level goals requires integrating information across existing administrative boundaries. For example, defining “pandemic preparedness” may involve considering, among many other things, global migration patterns, food and water supply, and state capacity. Goal setting also involves examining the interactions among systems: for some purposes, it may be appropriate to treat the climatic system and the public-health system as distinct; for others, less so. These meta-level questions demand resolution by an omnicompetent body capable of viewing systems as wholes. In the 1960s and 70s, scholars called for something similar: administrative bodies capable of taking “a systems or holistic approach” to public policy.33 But no such institution emerged with more than “relatively limited” powers.34 Despite its very different intellectual orientation, OIRA might now fill the gap. OIRA, of course “has come under sustained criticism almost since the inception of regulatory review.”35 But it nonetheless has the distinct advantage here of an existing trans-substantive mandate. Moreover, goal setting should be responsive to the regulatory review process I describe below. Therefore, any substitute for OIRA would substantially have to replicate its functions while somehow avoiding its flaws. Reform seems the easier path.

Setting goals for structural-risk regulation would only extend existing practice. Since 1993, federal agency representatives have been required to coordinate their proposed rulemaking agendas for the coming year with the Executive Office of the President.36 And twice each year, OIRA publishes the Unified Agenda, which notes agencies’ planned regulatory and deregulatory activity.37 High-level, pre-rulemaking coordination structures therefore already exist. These structures could be repurposed to facilitate the creation of systems-level goals. Doing so would represent an extension of Executive Order 12,866’s stated ambition of providing for “coordination of regulations,” alongside merely “promot[ing] the President’s priorities.”38

Principle #2: The process of choosing system-level goals should reinforce democratic values.

There are strong reasons, magnified by the distinctive features of structural risks, for this goal-setting process to reinforce democracy. Here again, E.O. 12,866 provides a model, with its call for “maximiz[ing] consultation and the resolution of potential conflicts at an early stage” and “involv[ing] the public and its State, local, and tribal officials in regulatory planning.”39

Democracies, as I claimed above, should respect citizens’ freedom and equality. But because they concern citizens as such, they should do so systemically, not necessarily in each of their constituent institutions. What matters is whether the polity as a whole is democratic, not, say, whether the Environmental Protection Agency taken alone is democratic.40 This means that “reinforcing” democracy through goal setting need not mean directly “democratizing” goal setting. Like Samuel Bagg and Udit Bhatia,41 I do not believe democracy must be “isomorphic,” replicating the same institutional principles in every case. In this sense, goal setting need not become a “forum for democratic agency,”42 even if it promotes democratic agency overall.

The principled reason for reinforcing democracy through systemic goal setting is that expertise alone is generally insufficient to justify choices among system-level goals. Regulatory decisions may sometimes be defended on technocratic grounds—for example, that they efficiently achieve certain ends. But in making systemic choices, ends are not given. These decisions require determining, say, what makes an economy “sustainable” and why sustainability is valuable in the first place. Here there is likely to be reasonable, nontechnical disagreement. Some may perceive environmental justice as partly constitutive of sustainability; others may see them as distinct. Of course, “[a]gencies are themselves the products of a democratic process,” not an alien imposition.43 Regulators may therefore have sufficient normative democratic authority to make these choices. But if regulators are to answer value questions, then (all else equal) they should do so in ways that deepen democracy. That is, regulators should embrace procedures reflecting their respect for citizens’ capacity for judgment and sustaining that respect into the future.44

Democracy’s importance here is increased by structural risks’ long-term significance. Because today’s regulatory decisions may decisively affect tomorrow’s prospects, policies made now may therefore appear as a “dead hand” reaching from the past to govern the future. To some extent, this is inevitable: every political choice affects the future, and none is strictly costless to reverse. But with respect to “major” decisions—and especially those whose significance tends to grow over time—democratic legitimacy is particularly important, in two respects.45 First, to the extent that perceived political identity is continuous, democratic decision-making today may help future citizens see our choices as “their own.”46 In this sense, today’s democracy may sustain desirable forms of political agency. Second, technocratic decision-making may foreclose future democratic decision-making. Institutional design itself frequently exhibits increasing returns.47 It may therefore prove difficult to recover democratic agency once lost, and citizens may find themselves unable to change regulatory course.

These intertemporal considerations also suggest the pragmatic reason for endorsing democratic procedures: systemic stability requires both social trust and trust in government.48 In general, complex systems are characterized by substantial uncertainty.49 In social systems in particular, managing this uncertainty frequently requires trust: trust facilitates forbearance from conduct that may be individually rational but collectively destructive. For example, regulations concerning artificial-intelligence research, or restricting research of solar geoengineering, may be undermined by “rogue” researchers skeptical of the government’s decisions. Trust is especially important when policy makers are seeking to effect systemic change, since uncertainty is likely to be especially great during the transitional period. And after transitional periods, when decisions may be partly “locked in,” social trust facilitates citizens’ reconciliation with the status quo. Successful political institutions generally foster both social and political trust.50 In particular, citizens who value democracy place more trust in governments they perceive as highly democratic.51 And political trust, in turn, contributes to the effective implementation of public policy.52

Trust and trustworthiness are especially important in view of the epistemic challenges involved in regulation. Not only is technical expertise alone unable to answer important value questions, it is crucially limited on its own terms, as political scientist Samuel DeCanio has argued. In general, the administrative state is hindered by the “singularity” of its decisions: there is “no rival organization with the authority to produce legally binding rules that are compulsory for all members of its geographically defined territory.”53 This lack of rivals means that there are “no observable policy counterfactuals within the territory the state controls.”54 It is therefore difficult to infer the causal effects of administrative decisions and hence also difficult to assess their efficiency. These concerns are exacerbated for policies affecting complex systems, given the epistemic challenges they pose even under ideal conditions. The consequence of all this is that regulatory decisions might not earn sociological legitimacy on the basis of their causal efficacy. Instead, some other means of legitimation may be necessary. Democracy, I have suggested, can help supply it.

I offer three complementary ways that OIRA can reinforce democracy through the goal-setting process. These proposals reflect my contextual judgment, rather than any putatively general answer to the “democracy question.”55 I aim only to illustrate how agencies might justify procedural reforms in terms of citizens’ freedom and equality, not to settle contested theoretical and institutional debates.56

First, and most ambitiously, OIRA should open goal setting to greater public participation.57 Here, there are opportunities to experiment, including by introducing “lottocratic” institutions. In recent years, some political theorists have argued that some political power should be shifted to assemblies of randomly selected citizens.58 Where they have been convened, these assemblies usually gather for specific purposes and for limited times and incorporate expert presentations. The core idea is that these lottocratic bodies may better represent what the citizenry at large wants, as compared to elected legislatures. Citizen assemblies are not perfect; indeed, they remain vulnerable to capture by special interests.59 But they may still have a limited but beneficial role within the administrative state.60 In particular, citizen assemblies may offer administrators an additional “picture” of public opinion, one less shaped by the limitations of polling or the latest developments in partisan messaging.61 And depending upon how they are structured, citizen assemblies may facilitate deliberation between citizens and administrators, encouraging greater governmental responsiveness to citizens’ reasoning.62

Second, OIRA should promote deliberation among agencies in setting systems-level goals. Interagency consultation is a familiar feature of administrative law,63 and OIRA already plays a leading role in facilitating it.64 Consultation’s specifically democratic potential, however, has been underappreciated.65 In many statutory contexts, interagency consultation serves two main purposes: it ensures that decisions are made after discussion with those possessing relevant expertise and it delays actions that may have unintended consequences. In systemic goal setting, its function can be different. Like citizen assemblies, administrative agencies can be understood as representing the citizenry: they effect democratically determined purposes, working out their implications in ways that reflect both ordinary politics and enduring principles. Consultation and collaboration among agencies allow these fragmentary images of “the people” to coalesce. Together, they can provide a more complete picture.66 Whereas ordinary regulatory coordination may benefit “lead agencies” as first movers, goal setting can accommodate deliberation on terms reflecting the importance of agencies’ claims and the depth of those claims’ popular support. The result would be a process that better reflects citizens’ varied commitments.

Third, and finally, OIRA should implicitly acknowledge the limits on the President’s democratic authority, even as it continues to foster forms of “presidential administration.”67 The President can rightly claim to be “a spokesperson for public opinion” when guiding the execution of the laws—but only a spokesperson.68 Public opinion can, does, and should manifest in other ways, as I have just suggested. Recognizing other sources of democratic authority would help constrain the President’s own claims. This should partly be a matter of role morality: OIRA staff should understand their work in terms beyond the familiar synthesis of “external political control” by the President and “internal professionalism.”69 But recognizing the limits of “presidential administration” should also involve openness to setting systems-level goals through procedures that encourage “full and fair ventilation of reasons for action in changing contexts that resist hierarchical control.”70 So understood, OIRA’s claim to lead in goal setting would be based not upon its political stature but upon its capacity to integrate various forms of professional knowledge and political claims.71

Principle #3: The process of developing structural-risk regulations should reinforce democratic values.

Democracy is valuable not only in choosing systemic goals but also in selecting means for achieving them. Policy making, no less than goal setting, involves contested value questions; the moral legitimacy of those decisions must be maintained over long time scales; and implementing public policy over those time scales requires maintaining social trust. In some respects, administrative law already reflects these concerns: in comparative terms, notice-and-comment rulemaking is an unusually participatory process, despite its imperfections.72 Regulatory review, however, can help ensure that rulemaking procedures advance democracy, beyond what is required by law.

Regulatory review already considers procedure, but not for democratic reasons.73 OIRA routinely asks agencies to list alternatives to its proposed rules during notice-and-comment and to seek public comments on specific issues.74 These requests, however, generally serve epistemic rather than moral purposes: they mostly help ensure that agencies have sufficient information. OIRA does also serve a “Frankfurterian” role, as a guardian of “fair process,” including by encouraging “participation by a large number of people inside and outside the federal government.”75 But this role typically involves neither explicit consideration of political morality nor substantial additions to settled administrative practice.

Regulatory reviewers interested in promoting democracy should begin by critically assessing the statutory context. In general, as I noted above, the administrative state claims legitimate democratic authority through statute. But for any particular agency action, even one authorized by law, statutory authority may be more or less democratically robust. For example, a relatively recent statute vindicating citizens’ equality may provide a robust democratic basis for regulation, even if it asks administrators to answer complicated value questions. In administering this statute, regulators may not need to do much more to deepen democracy; following ordinary procedures may suffice. By contrast, an older statute inconsistent with subsequent democratic practice may be on shakier ground, even if its scope is narrower.76 In executing these laws, regulators should be especially attentive to democratic values. Judging statutes as more or less democratic will not be easy. But lawyers can help technical experts mediate between scientific, institutional, and moral considerations.77 And over time, regulatory reviewers may become more accustomed to deliberating in terms of democracy.

Recognizing possible democratic deficits in agency authority does not mean conceding that regulatory proposals implicate “major questions.” In West Virginia v. EPA, the U.S. Supreme Court explained that in “certain extraordinary cases,” an “agency must point to ‘clear congressional authorization’ for the power it claims.”78 These cases are identifiable by “‘the ‘history and the breadth of the authority that [the agency] has asserted[]’ and the ‘economic and political significance’ of that assertion.’”79 This interpretive inquiry is distinct from the normative inquiry I have recommended to administrators. To be sure, structural-risk regulations will often be of great “economic and political significance.” But even claims of regulatory authority with robust precedents may be democratically deficient if those precedents failed to advance citizens’ freedom and equality. Agencies could therefore conclude that democracy promotion is appropriate in developing structural-risk regulations, without signaling to courts that it is claiming newly broad authority.

After examining the statutory context, regulatory reviewers should ask agency staff to justify their procedural choices in democratic terms. In general, procedure and substance are “interdependent variables in the constrained optimization problem” of regulatory policy making.80 That is, an agency’s preferred procedures depend in part upon the substance of the policies it pursues, and vice versa. This implies that regulatory review focusing on one to the exclusion of the other might miss a significant part of the picture. And this is no less true for review focused on democratic values. In practice, engaging in “democratic review” might involve OIRA asking line agencies to consider the same democratizing reforms I discussed above. Citizen assemblies and interagency dialogue might usefully complement statutory procedures in some contexts.

Two caveats apply here.81 First, OIRA should not categorically demand any particular extra-statutory procedures for developing structural-risk regulations. In shifting from setting goals to selecting means, it will matter more exactly which structural risk agencies are trying to manage. For example, solar geoengineering and artificial intelligence might both involve structural risks, but regulations for the two will look rather different. Precisely because substance and procedure are interdependent, it is difficult to make general determinations about the procedures most appropriate across regulatory domains. Citizen assemblies and interagency consultation should be salient options for promoting democracy in policy making, but they may not be appropriate in every case.

Second, though OIRA should remain a “guardian of a well-functioning administrative process,”82 it should not be overly demanding. OIRA is mostly staffed by regulatory generalists, while line agencies are staffed by subject-matter specialists. This means that there are important informational asymmetries between the two, and the gap cannot always easily be bridged.83 In general, observers tend to note these asymmetries in technical contexts: an EPA staffer, for example, may have devoted decades to understanding some pollutant. But if substance and procedure are interdependent, then the asymmetry matters more broadly as well. Whatever advantage OIRA officials have over line-agency staff with respect to regulatory procedure is limited by their disadvantage with respect to regulatory substance, since the two are not fully separable.84 OIRA’s capacity to democratize structural-risk regulation may therefore be limited, though still significant.

B. Substantive Principles

This subpart shifts from how structural-risk regulations should be developed to what they should do and offers three more principles for regulatory review. My central recommendation is that regulatory reviewers should assess (1) how new regulations are likely to alter the political environment and (2) how those political developments are likely to influence public policy. This inquiry, I argue, should be both positive and normative. In developing this recommendation, I show how emerging social-science research—apart from the economics expertise already well-represented in OIRA—can contribute to democratizing regulation.85

Principle #4: Regulation of structural risks should be democratically durable.

Regulators should attend not only to whether policies are formulated democratically but also to whether policies are democratically durable. Roughly speaking, I use “democratic durability” to refer to the idea that policies should be resistant to unintended changes driven by external circumstances but amenable to deliberate, democratic adjustment. This, in turn, combines two related aims.

First, policies should generally resist unintentional “drift.” “Drift” refers to “changes in the operation or effect of policies that occur without significant changes in those policies’ structure.”86 In general, drift occurs because the context in which policies operate changes. Drift may be either expansionary (e.g., the increase in Social Security Disability Insurance claimants between the 1950s and the 2010s)87 or contractionary (e.g., the decrease in unionized workers over a similar period).88 Expansion or contraction may sometimes be beneficial, depending upon the circumstances, and in some cases, policy makers may intentionally use leverage drift for their purposes. But when drift is unanticipated, its benefits are merely fortuitous. Policy expansion is likely to impose undue costs; policy contraction, to achieve insufficient benefits.

Second, policies should reinforce democratic values over time. Whether a political decision is democratic depends not only upon how it was made but also upon what it does and how it is implemented. In particular, even laws enacted democratically can prove anti-democratic over the long run if they undermine future democratic agency. In some cases, such as filling a wetland, democratic concerns may arise because decisions wholly foreclose some choices, no matter who would make them.89 In others, such as authorizing presidential emergency powers, problems may result from decisions’ effects on the distribution of political power. Policies limiting democratic agency may still be desirable, all things considered.90 But insofar as democracy is valuable, there are always pro tanto reasons to avoid such constraints.

Both aspects of democratic durability are especially important for structural-risk regulations. First, consider drift resistance. For policies to resist drift need not mean that they never change. Rather, it can also mean that they change along with the circumstances through built-in adaptation mechanisms while maintaining the same “structure.”91 Drift resistance, then, can be “dynamic” as well as “static.” Because structural risks exhibit increasing returns and threaten greater harm over time, it is especially important that structural-risk regulations be dynamically drift resistant. For example, policies causing brief, one-time reductions in greenhouse gas emissions may (or may not) be beneficial. But their efficacy will be limited because greenhouse gases will persist in the atmosphere and fossil-fuel infrastructure will remain in use. By contrast, drift resistance is less crucial for risks that do not increase or become costlier to avoid over time.92

Regulations’ substance bears upon democratic values in much the same ways as does the regulatory process. Respecting citizens’ freedom and equality means respecting it over time: future generations must not be unduly burdened by the “dead hand of the past.” Structural-risk regulations—even just by virtue of their sheer significance—can entrench new distributions of power, whether formally or functionally.93 To the extent these distributions prevent future citizens from being governed in ways that respect their freedom and equality, they are objectionable on democratic grounds. Moreover, structural-risk regulations’ significance heightens these objections’ importance. Making collective decisions in terms of freedom and equality is most valuable when those choices affect the very structure of society, the economy, the environment, or other large-scale systems.94

I propose two complementary methods for pursuing democratic durability in structural-risk regulation, which I call “policy-feedback analysis” and “democratic-feedback analysis.” Both would improve regulatory review by incorporating and extending techniques now emerging in political science and other disciplines.95

Policy-feedback and democratic-feedback analysis correspond, respectively, to resistance to drift and preservation of democratic agency. Policy-feedback analysis would ask: how are certain policies likely to affect the political context in which those policies operate, and how are those changes likely to affect the operation of those policies? Democratic-feedback analysis would likewise start with an examination of the political consequences of policy choices, but then would inquire: how are those political changes likely to promote or hinder democratic values? (Here, then, “democratic agency” refers not to any strong form of collective self-government, but only to political agency exercised through institutions justifiable in terms of citizens’ freedom and equality.) Both policy-feedback and democratic-feedback analysis would formalize some of the considerations that already inform policy development, while also encouraging long-term analyses of whether and how “new policies” will create “new politics.”96

Policy-feedback analysis presumes that while sociopolitical dynamics are not fully predictable, the forces governing them can be sufficiently well understood to inform regulation.97 In particular, I emphasize three major determinants of feedback effects: policy instruments (i.e., the proposals under review), initial conditions, and feedback mechanisms. These can be modeled together to develop an account of a policy’s likely effects over time.98 Whether these “models” will be relatively formal and quantitative or relatively informal and qualitative depends upon the scientific and social-scientific “state of the art.” For this reason, particular modeling techniques may be feasible in some areas but not in others.

In focusing on policy instruments, I emphasize that feedback effects may not be uniform across a given regulation. For example, an agency may promulgate a legislative rule that includes both an ambient standard and a public-disclosure requirement for the same pollutant. Though these requirements might work in tandem, there is no ex ante reason to assume that their political consequences will be the same. Each will have its own cost–benefit structure, and each may empower different groups in different ways.99 These effects might then interact, creating further complexities. Regulatory reviewers should therefore consider proposed regulations both as bundles of separate instruments and as interconnected systems.100

Policy-feedback mechanisms and initial conditions are both capacious categories. The major mechanisms are (1) resource/incentive mechanisms, which alter the resources available to actors and/or influence which choices are available to them, and (2) interpretive mechanisms, which alter information flows and, as a result, shape how actors interpret the world.101 Feedback from these mechanisms may be either positive (i.e., self-reinforcing) or negative (i.e., self-undermining). Much political behavior could fall under these labels. For example, developing administrative capacity, directing funds to interest groups, or imposing criminal sanctions might all count as “resource/incentive mechanisms”; distributing propaganda, providing technical training, or changing social norms might all be “interpretive mechanisms.” Similarly, relevant initial conditions can include anything related to “resources” or “information.”

Because policy-feedback dynamics will often be complex, regulatory reviewers should seek outside input in constructing their models. Following recent work modeling sociopolitical feedbacks in the climate system,102 I propose that regulatory reviewers convene interdisciplinary workshops to identify which particular mechanisms are most germane to particular structural risks.103 They may also glean useful information from the institutions I have recommended for setting systemic goals, including citizen assemblies and interagency consultation. With respect to “ordinary” citizens in particular, there is good reason to think that current administrative practice underrates the epistemic resources available. Under the right conditions, the cognitive diversity of “the many” can prove valuable.104

Democratic-feedback analysis would involve subjecting the conclusions of policy-feedback analysis to normative scrutiny. This would involve difficult theoretical questions—most obviously, what counts as democratic or undemocratic?105 And even where there is broad agreement on definitions, applications might prove vexing. For example, a policy might empower some interest groups over others but reduce material inequalities as a result. In cases like this, what “democracy” requires might be unclear.106

Despite these challenges, democratic-feedback analysis would offer two main benefits. First, like cost–benefit analysis, it would force regulatory reviewers to make their considerations explicit. This process alone may be valuable: even if OIRA staff, for example, are already thinking about the democratic implications of proposed policies, they may miss certain considerations simply because they are not putting their thoughts to paper. Democratic-feedback analysis could not guarantee good normative theorizing, but it would probably secure better results than leaving moral reasoning implicit. Second, and relatedly, democratic-feedback analysis can “mak[e] bureaucracies think”107 about the democratic consequences of their choices. Regulatory reviewers often conceive of themselves as relatively apolitical.108 Democratic-feedback analysis would encourage them to become “political” in the specific sense of being explicitly committed to advancing citizens’ freedom and equality.

Three considerations suggest that these benefits are attainable, despite the theoretical challenges. First, administrative actors already engage in noneconomic normative deliberation. For example, Executive Order 13,563 permits agencies considering regulations to weigh “values” intimately connected to democracy, including “equity, human dignity, fairness, and distributive impacts.”109 Scholarship on “administrative constitutionalism” has also shown that, long before the Executive Order, administrative actors “elaborat[ed] … new constitutional understandings” relevant to democratic values.110 Second, and more theoretically, advancing democracy does not require endorsing some comprehensive democratic ideal. It is enough to offer reasons for democracy’s real-world value and then to promote policies and institutions that reflect those reasons.111 Certainly, existing regulatory practice does not presume that making decisions requires resolving every theoretical disagreement. Finally, enhancing public participation in rulemaking—as I proposed above—can help regulatory reviewers develop workable conceptions of democracy. Democracy itself would be subject to democratic deliberation.

The Administrative Procedure Act does not foreclose this deliberation. Scholars have debated whether and how judges should credit regulators’ political considerations when engaging in “arbitrary and capricious” review.112 But regardless of whether they merit deference, “political” decisions are permissible—at least where they are otherwise justifiable. Indeed, in Department of Commerce v. New York, the U.S. Supreme Court explained: “Agency policymaking is not a ‘rarified technocratic process, unaffected by political considerations or the presence of Presidential power,’” and the Administrative Procedure Act does not treat it as such.113 That case, together with Department of Homeland Security v. Regents of the University of California,114 suggests a central concern in judicial doctrine for enhancing political accountability.115 To the extent that policy-feedback and democratic-feedback review encourage accountability over time, they comport with the broad thrust of recent case law.116

Principle #5: Regulation of structural risks should incorporate triggers for review and revision.

Though policy-feedback and democratic-feedback analyses aim to provide holistic assessments of regulations’ democratic durability, it may also be helpful for officials to have rules of thumb for regulatory design. Here is one: in general, structural-risk regulations should include triggers for their own review and revision to facilitate democratic agency. That is, regulations should include provisions requiring either new deliberation or new policy-making processes, effective upon some predetermined date or upon some other change in the regulated system.117

Regulatory triggers can help fill a potential lacuna in democratic-feedback analysis. Democracy, political theorist Jan-Werner Müller has explained, “has a dual nature”: “First, it requires a designated locus (and specific times) for collectively binding decision making,” and second, it needs “a place for the continuous formation of opinions and political judgments in society at large.”118 Democratic-feedback analysis will likely fare better at weighing the latter than the former. Regulatory reviewers may be able to predict whom a policy might empower in the public sphere but not how it will affect decision-making. Regulatory triggers provide no certainty about future decisions’ content, but they can help ensure that decisions will be made. This information will often be important to assessing a proposal’s likely democratic credentials over the long run.

Regulatory triggers, like policy-feedback and democratic-feedback analysis, would especially suit structural-risk regulations. In every domain, changing circumstances can demand new policy responses. But structural risks demand particular flexibility, in view of their significant possible nonlinearities. In some cases, more stringent regulations may urgently become necessary; in others, regulations may quickly become obsolete. In other words, the threat of policy drift is likely to loom even when regulations are designed to be politically resilient. And drift, in turn, can have significant political consequences. Nonlinear increases in risk can create “states of exception,” in which ordinary legal principles are suspended and power can be abused.119 Triggers can help policy regimes adjust before disaster strikes.

Current regulatory schemes often do not respond adequately to these challenges. Regulations do generally contain conditional provisions. For example, a workplace-safety rule may apply only to employers with at least 100 employees. These schemes make application of law responsive to changes in the world: when an employer hires its 100th employee, it becomes subject to the rule. But this responsiveness is often limited. It exists within a broadly stable policy framework and is given effect primarily through enforcement. Regulatory triggers today therefore do not tend to offer new forums for democratic agency. They also offer only limited protection against policy drift: insofar as regulatory triggers apply only to particular regions or parties, they may ignore the interdependencies characteristic of structural risks.

It would be preferable to formulate triggers for large-scale review and revision of regulations. These would provide “thresholds of alarm” responsive to systems-level information.120 Regulatory thresholds should probably not be based upon new, comprehensive risk assessments—otherwise the costs of delay would be too great—but instead upon previously known indicia of systemic risk. Here the “planetary boundaries” framework in earth science is illustrative. That approach defines the “safe operating space” for humanity as a whole by identifying several quantitative “boundaries.”121 The boundary variables are interconnected, exhibiting both positive and negative feedback effects. It is possible to develop policies that use boundaries of this sort as regulatory triggers: when certain thresholds are crossed, new rules could take effect. Crucially, these new rules need not be incremental adjustments to existing rules. Substantially different regulatory frameworks may be better suited for new realities.

Regulatory triggers of this sort would be roughly akin to legislative “hammers.” For example, the “take title” provision of the Low-Level Radioactive Waste Policy Amendment of 1985 provided that if the states did not meet certain deadlines for providing for nuclear-waste disposal, the states themselves must take title to and possession of the waste and assume liability for associated damages.122 The “take title” provision therefore effectively created an initial, default regulatory regime and an alternative, conditional one. The former encouraged states to facilitate private waste disposal; the latter required states to handle disposal themselves. Taking inspiration from this structure, regimes governing structural risks could, for example, have triggers for switching from market-based to command-and-control instruments. Or they could extend regulations to new domains not initially covered. Regulations could also become less stringent and more flexible as needed, departing from the “hammer” model.

Principle #6: Administrators should be cautious in conducting cost–benefit analysis for structural-risk regulations.

Cost–benefit analysis may be of relatively limited use in assessing systemic-risk regulations in general and structural-risk regulations in particular. Rather than dominating regulatory review, cost–benefit analysis should be “only one input into public policy.”123

Costs and benefits cannot easily be calculated for systemically significant policies. I noted earlier that because the consequences of individual decisions depend upon their systemic context, it is difficult to aggregate component-level choices to obtain systems-level objectives. For the same reason, it is not easy to anticipate the consequences of any component-level choice when the system is subject to significant change. This point is most intuitive when considering policy questions that are “so complex or large-scale that it is impossible to competently forecast the costs or benefits of a proposed regulation:”124 these regulations may “alter the constellation of relative outputs and prices over the whole economy,” such that the rest of the world cannot be held constant.125 But even apparently smaller choices can frustrate the policy calculus. “[S]ystem-wide costs and benefits that accumulate over time” can eventually “change the fundamental character of society.”126

Regulatory reviewers should ask whether policies are likely either to effect system-wide change or to take effect amid system-wide change. If they are, then reviewers should take special caution in using cost–benefit analysis. By contrast, where policies would cause more incremental adjustments or where the economic and social system is likely to remain relatively stable, cost–benefit analysis may be relatively unproblematic.127 In counseling caution in some cases, I do not embrace the categorical conclusion that “CBA is not an appropriate tool” in assessing structural risks.128 For one thing, the risk of systemic change (even if unintended) is never zero; it is always possible that the background conditions enabling cost–benefit analysis could disappear. There is therefore no sharp, ex ante distinction between cases where cost–benefit analysis is appropriate and those where it is not. Moreover, alternative decision procedures (including those I have outlined here) are not costless.129 Cost–benefit analysis’s limitations do not alone determine its proper role, absent consideration of what could replace it.

Regulators may sometimes be able to integrate policy-feedback and cost-benefit analysis. Policy-feedback analysis aims to anticipate the interactions between proposed regulations and their political contexts, in both directions. So understood, it is, in part, a study of regulatory efficacy.130 In some cases, efficacy will be understood in relative terms—for example, by comparison to the intentions of a program’s creators. But in other cases, efficacy may be absolute. Policy-feedback analysis may suggest that the net benefits of some policy are likely to change over time, and these changes may be quantifiable (if only roughly). Where quantification is possible, there should be no firm boundary between policy-feedback and cost–benefit analysis. Cost–benefit analysis can provide an initial assessment of a program’s cost structure. This assessment can inform predictions about its policy feedbacks, and these, in turn, can reveal more costs and benefits.

More speculatively, regulators might also refine cost–benefit analysis in light of democratic decision-making. Cost–benefit analysis generally assigns values “through direct use of, or in analogy with, the logic of market allocation.”131 Market valuation may have merits in some contexts. But it cannot easily value goods that citizens treat “specifically” as “social concern[s],” particularly with respect to existence values.132 For these goods, political processes offer an alternative mechanism of valuation. Politics is, of course, flawed: it cannot reliably aggregate individual preferences with any precision, and even if it could, it would not perfectly capture the sorts of ideal, public-minded judgments that critics of cost–benefit analysis seek.133 Still, regulatory reviewers may credit democratic procedures—both legislative and regulatory—as providing rough guidance on appropriate quantitative valuation. This guidance will usually be qualitative, though recent research indicates the potential for gleaning quantitative information from democratic norms as well.134

In this part, I respond to some possible concerns. My aim here is not to insist that my proposed approach would be without drawbacks—no reforms would be—but instead to show that its problems would be manageable.

A. Personnel Constraints

The democratic approach could not easily be administered by current regulatory reviewers alone. Some of what I have proposed, such as considering the democratic credentials of agency procedures, would extend OIRA’s existing roles. But others, such as convening citizen assemblies or engaging in policy-feedback review, would be more novel. These tasks would require expertise not currently well-represented within OIRA. OIRA currently has career staff with graduate degrees in “economics, law, policy analysis, statistics, and information technology,” as well as various “technical fields.”135 Yet these subject areas, for all their value, do not exhaust insight into the distinctively political considerations I have described here. Without adequate personnel, the federal government would likely lack sufficient state capacity to undertake the full panoply of democratizing reforms.136

Staffing should not be viewed as an insuperable barrier. President Biden’s “Modernizing Regulatory Review” memorandum directs the OMB Director to “consider ways that OIRA can play a more proactive role in partnering with agencies” to pursue beneficial regulations and to “identify reforms that will promote the efficiency, transparency, and inclusiveness of the interagency review process.”137 These goals do not require OIRA reform, but they are highly open-ended. Increasing OIRA’s staff and broadening its professional diversity can be an effective strategy for meeting the President’s objectives. “Modernizing Regulatory Review” affords a rare opportunity to reflect upon OIRA’s structure: OIRA has consolidated its essential regulatory role over the last four decades, and it could now effectively manage the expansion of its ranks. In short, there is good reason not to treat the institutional status quo as fixed. “Modernization” need not consist solely of adopting new analytical techniques.

If the composition of OIRA and other agencies should not be taken as given, the challenge is determining who should join their ranks. Part of the answer lies in administrators’ academic backgrounds. Staff trained in political science, political economy, and political theory, for example, might have much to contribute to regulatory review. Yet these disciplines as currently constituted have their own limits. For example, political scientist Jacob S. Hacker notes that his field is ill-prepared to embrace “a policy mindset that takes seriously imbalances of power in the political economy, grapples with the challenge of building durable governing capacities, and focuses on the political as well as economic effects of public policies.”138 For now, it remains to identify personnel with the personal, professional, and intellectual attributes necessary for pursuing democratizing reforms.

B. Institutionalization

Worries about personnel also relate to a broader concern: large-scale administrative reforms require effective institutionalization. So far, I have been discussing political constraints much as though they applied only to policies administered, and not to administration itself. But OIRA, and the administrative state more broadly, is not insulated from the struggle for power.139 Nor is it immune to subtler pressures stemming from “the nonrational pressures that arise out of the administrative process,”140 including those related to “group identification, status, and relationship networks.”141 Dynamics political, cultural, or otherwise might generate resistance within agencies (including OIRA) to my proposed reforms.142 Even some who view my ideas sympathetically might think their development futile.

This objection points to the need for implementation to extend beyond OIRA. Just as the “economic style of reasoning” in public policy ascended only over decades,143 so, too, will institutionalizing alternatives take time. In part, this is a matter of how the reformers approach their task. To make changes in regulatory review “stick,” explains scholar and former OIRA official Bridget C.E. Dooling, “some combination of internal development, interagency review, external peer review, and public comment may help firm up the basis for the changes.”144 But though I have emphasized the promise of “Modernizing Regulatory Review,”145 any single presidential initiative is likely insufficient to support substantial change. Deeper reform would benefit, for example, from the support of higher-education institutions146 and professional networks.147 These, too, offer no panacea, not least because universities and professions have their own durable cultures.148 But they are nonetheless important forums for the larger project of making democratic equality more salient in regulation.

C. Regulatory Ossification

The democratic approach involves potentially burdensome new procedures. In regulatory review, no less than in other administrative contexts, procedure is no panacea.149 Perhaps most importantly, the “ossification” associated with bureaucratic process might prove greater than whatever benefits that process brings.150 This concern is especially significant with respect to structural risks, given that their harms can quickly multiply. And it is exacerbated still further by the current combination of political polarization and growing “anti-administrativism:”151 if a new rule is delayed, the next presidential administration may be unwilling or unable to carry forward its promulgation.

“Ossification” is a serious concern, but the process costs of the democratic approach need not be too high. Most important here is what the democratic approach does not involve: expanded judicial review. Some have argued that judges should accord or withhold deference based upon the democratic quality of agencies’ decision-making processes.152 But whatever the judiciary’s proper role, it does not determine the executive’s. I have argued only for new forms of review by OIRA staff, not by judges, and the former would not lead to new litigation delays. Moreover, much as OIRA’s staff need not remain fixed, neither need its procedures. OIRA could still review agencies’ decisions not to regulate.153 If necessary, the OIRA Administrator could waive review of significant regulations to prevent harmful delay.154 And over time, OIRA could collaborate with agencies to develop more efficient review practices.

D. Political Capture

Concerns about capture mainly take two related forms. First, some might object to “politicizing” regulatory review. Under the previous presidential administration, cost–benefit analysis was “subject to flagrant manipulation.”155 Further politicizing regulatory review—even in democracy’s name—may seem like a risky proposition, especially in the context of structural risks. Indeed, one advantage of regulatory review might lie precisely in stabilizing otherwise-contentious regulatory processes with the technical language of costs and benefits. Second, some might be more open in principle to politicization but worry that mechanisms meant to promote democracy would in fact facilitate regulatory capture.156 Multiplying the channels for influence over public policy might only serve the powerful.

Capture is indeed a concern, but not one the democratic approach would likely exacerbate. It is true that my proposals would introduce novel considerations into regulatory review. But there is little new danger in politicizing what has always been political. OIRA had an anti-regulatory bent for decades, notwithstanding strong policy arguments to the contrary.157 If anything, the democratic approach might counteract certain forms of politicization by embedding within OIRA pro-democratic and pro-regulatory commitments at odds with the office’s historical tendencies. For similar reasons, my proposals should not be particularly vulnerable to capture. The democratic approach would not propagate procedural safeguards against abuse of state power. Rather, it would aim to channel that power toward particular substantive purposes, relying mostly on administrators themselves. To the extent my suggestions would create new opportunities for influence, they would be designed to resist the influence of special interests. Corruption is always possible, but I believe the reforms I outline would not make it worse.

More generally, the framework I have developed is flexible. In proposing that administrators consult assemblies of randomly selected citizens, for example, I suggested they do so for only limited purposes.158 But my underlying point was that the process of developing structural-risk regulations should reflect and reinforce citizens’ freedom and equality. If it turns out that “lottocracy” has more potential to accomplish this than I have recognized, I have no basic objection to expanding assemblies’ role. Similarly, I argued that administrators could help promote democratic equality by influencing regulations’ design.159 It is possible that some might construe “democracy” to support empowering certain private interests over the public interest.160 Nothing could prevent all error. But this only underscores the importance of addressing the problems of personnel and institutionalization. Ultimately, sufficiently powerful coalitions, both within and outside the administrative state, must come to support reform. This is a serious challenge for implementation but not for the theoretical position that sustaining democracy requires attending to the political effects of public policy.

Scholars have argued (and argued) about cost–benefit analysis. They have grappled, too, with the “democracy question”161 in the administrative state. And they have certainly subjected OIRA to scrutiny. Yet so far, they have largely neglected democracy’s place in regulatory review.

I have offered a new approach. I have argued that, in confronting some of the planet’s most important challenges, democratic values can and should be embedded in regulations’ design. My proposals are hardly radical: they presume that federal regulators will continue to have an essential policy-making role. But they would require a reorientation: from instrumental to normative reasoning, from economics to political science. To guide this shift, I have refined the concepts we use to analyze important policy challenges, identifying a category of “structural risks.” I have outlined a new process for confronting these challenges, from setting broad goals to choosing regulatory specifics. I have shown how recent studies of policy feedback can inform the regulatory process. And I have proposed that an ideal of “democratic durability”: resistance to exogenous, nondemocratic change—and not just “efficacy,” conventionally understood—should be regulators’ lodestar when addressing structural risks.

This article has also raised questions for future research. Some are more conceptual: How should we understand the history of efforts to reform the administrative state from within, and what can that history tell us about reform efforts today?162 How should we understand democracy’s place in regulatory review outside the context of structural risks? What would democratic durability require given various other conceptions of democracy? Other questions are more institutional: How should courts treat regulators’ efforts to ensure democratic durability? How should regulators negotiate among different conceptions of democracy? What practical obstacles impede the pursuit of democratic durability? Beyond these lie still other questions of application and of methodological refinement.

I have not endeavored to answer all these. Rather, I have aimed to suggest new avenues for theory and practice. Democracy, I hope I have shown, need not be at odds with rational regulation. Indeed, in a society committed to citizens’ freedom and equality, it should be at regulation’s very core.

1 

I focus here on cost–benefit analysis, though in some cases it may be barred or otherwise irrelevant. See, e.g., Whitman v. Am. Trucking Assocs., Inc., 531 U.S. 457, 464–69 (2001) (holding that § 109(b)(1) of the Clean Air Act prohibits the Environmental Protection Agency from considering costs in setting ambient air quality standards).

2 

For a few examples just from the legal literature, see Cass R. Sunstein, Arbitrariness Review and Climate Change, 170 U. Pa. L. Rev. 991 (2022); David A. Weisbach & Cass R. Sunstein, Climate Change and Discounting the Future: A Guide for the Perplexed, 27 Yale L. & Poly Rev. 433 (2009); Symposium on Intergenerational Equity and Discounting, 74 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1 (2007); Daniel A. Farber, From Here to Eternity: Environmental Law and Future Generations, 2003 U. Ill. L. Rev. 289 (2003); Richard L. Revesz, Environmental Regulation, Cost–Benefit Analysis, and the Discounting of Human Lives, 99 Colum. L. Rev. 941 (1999).

3 

See, e.g., Douglas A. Kysar, Regulating from Nowhere ch. 6 (2010); Noah M. Sachs, Rescuing the Strong Precautionary Principle from Its Critics, 2011 U. Ill. L. Rev. 1285, 1321 (2011); Laurence H. Tribe, Ways Not to Think About Plastic Trees: New Foundations for Environmental Law, 83 Yale L. J. 1315, 1319 (1974); cf. Jedediah Purdy, Our Place in the World: A New Relationship for Environmental Ethics and Law, 62 Duke L. J. 857 (2013) (discussing Kysar’s and Tribe’s work). For a useful discussion of ethical issues salient to social-welfare calculations (including discounting), see Marc Fleurbaey et al., The Social Cost of Carbon: Valuing Inequality, Risk, and Population for Climate Policy, 102 Monist 84 (2019).

4 

For an exception, see K. Sabeel Rahman, Policymaking as Power-Building, 27 S. Cal. Interdisc. L. J. 315 (2018).

5 

Memorandum on Modernizing Regulatory Review, 86 Fed. Reg. 7223 (Jan. 26, 2021).

6 

Id. at 7224.

7 

See Robert Kuttner, Reclaiming the Deep State, Am. Prospect (Oct. 4, 2022), https://prospect.org/day-one-agenda/oira-reclaiming-the-deep-state/. Revesz’s defenses of cost–benefit analysis “ma[de] some on the left ambivalent about his appointment.” Id.

8 

Memorandum on Modernizing Regulatory Review, 86 Fed. Reg., at 7,224.

9 

The Biden Administration began pursuing some democratizing reforms soon after the Memorandum’s promulgation. See The White House, Fifth U.S. Open Government National Action Plan 7–9 (2022), https://open.usa.gov/assets/files/NAP5-fifth-open-government-national-action-plan.pdf (discussing the Administration’s plans for enhancing public engagement). In April 2023, the Administration announced a broader suite of changes. See Executive Order on Modernizing Regulatory Review (Apr. 6, 2023), https://www.whitehouse.gov/briefing-room/presidential-actions/2023/04/06/executive-order-on-modernizing-regulatory-review/; Request for Comments on Guidance Implementing Section 2(e) of the Executive Order of April 6, 2023 (Modernizing Regulatory Review), 88 Fed. Reg. 20916 (Apr. 7, 2023); Richard L. Revesz, Strengthening Our Regulatory System for the 21st Century, The White House (Apr. 6, 2023), https://www.whitehouse.gov/omb/briefing-room/2023/04/06/strengthening-our-regulatory-system-for-the-21st-century/. I take my reasoning here to be broadly congruent with that underlying the Administration’s plans. However, I do not offer any judgment as to particulars.

10 

Though my approach is new, I draw inspiration from and engage with recent work on the democratic theory of the administrative state beyond judicial review. See, e.g., Blake Emerson, The Publics Law (2019); K. Sabeel Rahman, Democracy Against Domination (2016); Daniel E. Walters, The Administrative Agon: A Democratic Theory for a Conflictual Regulatory State, 132 Yale L. J. 1 (2022).

11 

For a brief and clarifying discussion of the relationship between process and substance in the federal administrative state, see Emily S. Bremer & Sharon B. Jacobs, Agency Innovation in Vermont Yankee’s White Space, 32 J. Land Use & Envt L. 523, 525–27 (2017).

12 

Experimentation might be appropriate, for example, in light of different presidential administrations’ conceptions of democracy, policy priorities, and institutional constraints.

13 

For analyses of policy feedbacks in regulation, including by scholars outside the legal academy, see the sources cited at note 92 infra.

14 

This does not mean that every decision must be made by all citizens: there need be no disrespect in sometimes according more authority to some than to others, provided the allocations are made in the right way and for the right reasons.

15 

I do not assume that today’s government must be equally accountable to tomorrow’s citizens. I do, however, assume—to borrow a related point developed by political theorist Melissa Lane—that democracy “only count[s] as [a] full good[]” when pursued “in a sustainable manner.” Melissa Lane, Eco-Republic: What the Ancients Can Teach Us About Ethics, Virtue, and Sustainable Living 20 (2012). So understood, today’s decisions are less democratic to the extent that they undermine the possibility of tomorrow’s democratic decision-making.

16 

In part, the dispute would arise from the different purposes for which one might define the term “democracy.” For example, Niko Kolodny has defined a political decision as democratically made “when it is made by a process that gives everyone subject to it equal or both equal and positive, formal or both formal and informal opportunity for informed influence either over it or over decisions that delegate the making of it.” Rule Over None I: What Justifies Democracy?, 42 Phil. & Pub. Affs. 195, 197 (2014). I take this definition to be normatively “thinner” than mine: it presumes the theoretical relevance of “informed influence” but not any particular structure of justification for “democratic” decision-making. This is a virtue for Kolodny, since his aim is to ask what justifies democracy in general. Though “thin” definitions of democracy are appropriate for theoretical inquiries such as Kolodny’s, they generally offer little institutional guidance. My aim, however, is to justify (or reject) particular proposals offered within existing political structures, taking for granted that democracy can somehow be justified. I therefore opt for a “thicker” account, even at the risk of wrongly excluding otherwise-plausible accounts of democracy’s essence and value.

17 

See, e.g., Anna Stilz, Liberal Loyalty 59 (2009) (setting out the thesis that “the only kind of state that we could possibly have a genuine obligation to obey must be one based on a general will—a collective will that protects a set of common interests, and that imposes these protections in the form of an impersonal law”).

18 

See, e.g., James Lindley Wilson, Democratic Equality 17 (2019) (“A theory of political equality requires a reference to, and support from, an account of what social equality is and why it matters.”); Niko Kolodny, Rule Over None II: Social Equality and the Justification of Democracy, 42 Phil. & Pub. Affs. 287, 287 (2014) (“[T]he justification of democracy rests … on the fact that democracy is a particularly important constituent of a society in which people are related to one another as social equals, as opposed to social inferiors or superiors.”).

19 

Though my approach is ecumenical, it is not all-encompassing. For example, those who view democracy as requiring collective expression of popular will would hardly characterize my proposals for reform as particularly democratic. See, e.g., Richard Tuck, The Sleeping Sovereign (2016) (tracing this view in early-modern political thought). So, too, those who see democracy as always demanding grassroots participation. See, e.g., Carole Pateman, Participatory Democracy Revisited, 10 Persps. on Pol. 7, 15 (2012) (explaining that in “the conception of citizenship embodied in participatory democratic theory,” “[c]itizens have the right to public provision, the right to participate in decision-making about their collective life and to live within authority structures that make such participation possible.”). And while I justify certain reforms on “pragmatic” grounds—that is, in consequentialist terms that are presumptively distinguishable from democratic freedom and equality, but which I take would garner wide assent—I do not share “epistemic” democrats’ priority on determining optimal public policy See, e.g., Hélène Landemore, Democratic Reason: Politics, Collective Intelligence, and the Rule of the Many 1–2 (2012) (“[D]emocracy is a smart collective decision-making procedure that taps into the intelligence of the people as a group in ways that can even, under the right conditions, make it smarter than alternative regimes such as the rule of one or the rule of the few.”).

20 

Writing Competition, Legal Priorities Project, https://www.legalpriorities.org/competition.html (last visited Jan. 26, 2023). Future generations and existential risk are primary concerns of “longtermist” effective altruists, with whom the Legal Priorities Project is aligned. See Kieren Setiya, The New Moral Mathematics, Bos. Rev. (Aug. 15, 2022), https://www.bostonreview.net/articles/the-new-moral-mathematics/.

21 

I am invoking Executive Order on Modernizing Regulatory Review, supra note 9, though I do not mean to adopt its precise definition of that term.

22 

Though not essential, it is worth offering some broader intellectual context for my argument. I draw inspiration from my historical interpretation of the National Environmental Policy Act of 1969 (NEPA). Below, I offer a condensed summary of that interpretation. I develop it further in current work in progress.

Today, NEPA is best known as the source of the requirement to produce environmental impact statements (EISs) for “major” federal actions, but this was not always so. Instead, some—including most importantly political scientist Lynton K. Caldwell—hoped it would facilitate a holistic, “ecological” approach to federal policy making, one that would depend more upon administrative practices than judicial enforcement. See, e.g., Lynton K. Caldwell, 90th Cong., A National Policy for the Environment (Comm. Print 1968) [hereinafter Caldwell, A National Policy for the Environment]; see also Robert Cahn, Can Federal Law Help Citizens Save Nature’s Fragile Beauty?, Christian Sci. Monitor, Feb. 28, 1973, at 12 (describing the importance of EIS litigation as unanticipated by NEPA’s sponsors). Caldwell insisted that effective policy planning would involve “high-level coordinative structures … built around a few broad, simple, integrative concepts,” akin to the systems-level goal setting I describe below. Lynton K. Caldwell, Restructuring for Coordinative Policy and Action, 28 Pub. Admin. Rev. 301, 303 (1968). Drawing upon broader currents in environmental thought, he also noted the importance of political feedbacks. See Lynton K. Caldwell, Epilogue: Environment and the Shaping of Civilization 244, 254, in Congress and the Environment (Richard A. Cooley & Geoffrey Wandesforde-Smith eds., 1970). Yet Caldwell had a theoretical blind spot: he saw little value in democracy, endorsing instead a “biocratic” ideal oriented toward “dynamic homeostasis.” See Lynton K. Caldwell, Health and Homeostasis as Social Concepts: An Exploratory Essay 206, in Diversity and Stability in Ecological Systems (1969). Soon after NEPA’s enactment, environmental advocates broke from Caldwell, making NEPA a vehicle for EIS litigation and justifying these suits in democratic terms. See, e.g., Joseph L. Sax, The (Unhappy) Truth About NEPA, 26 Okla. L. Rev. 239, 245 (1973).

My work here responds to this tangled history. Critics now charge that EIS litigation can hinder rather than help environmental aims, see, e.g., J.B. Ruhl & James Salzman, What Happens When the Green New Deal Meets the Old Green Laws?, 44 Vt. L. Rev. 693 (2020), and distort rather than enhance democratic accountability, see Robert A. Kagan, Adversarial Legalism 249–50 (2019) (2001). In developing my “democratic approach,” I aim to recover something of Caldwell’s “ecological” orientation to public administration while giving higher priority to democratic values. And I try to do so without placing my hopes in “adversarial legalism.”

23 

Paul Pierson, Increasing Returns, Path Dependence, and the Study of Politics, 94 Am. Pol. Sci. Rev. 251, 252 (2000).

24 

Lynn M. LoPucki, Systems Approach to Law, 82 Cornell L. Rev. 479, 482 (1997).

25 

Cf. Stephen M. Gardiner, A Perfect Moral Storm: The Ethical Tragedy of Climate Change 38 (2011) (arguing that, in the context of climate change, “current populations may not be motivated to establish a fully adequate global regime. Given the temporal dispersion of effects—and especially the substantial deferral and backloading of impacts—such a regime is probably neither in their interests nor responsive to their concerns.”).

26 

See Bernard E. Harcourt, The Systems Fallacy: A Genealogy and Critique of Public Policy and Cost–Benefit Analysis, 47 J. Legal Studs. 419, 421 (2018) (arguing that “scope decisions” in systems analysis are “invariably normative and political in nature”). This suggests that determinations about which risks are “structural” should themselves be made democratically. Here, I believe the process of setting systemic goals may be helpful. Seeinfra Part II.A. Though my discussion below assumes a prior judgment about which risks to consider, it is likely that the deliberative procedures I describe would provide useful insight into the uses and disadvantages of “systems” or “structure” talk more broadly.

27 

See, e.g., Sheila Jasanoff, The Political Science of Risk Perception, 59 Reliability Eng.’g & Sys. Safety 91, 98 (1998) (“The conduct of risk perception research and the uses of such research in policy debates are bounded … by deeply entrenched political assumptions.”).

28 

Cf. Max Krahé, From System-Level to Investment-Level Sustainability: An Epistemological One-Way Street 21 (2021), https://www.academieroyale.be/Academie/documents/Opinio_SFPI_numerique31253.pdf (“[T]he sustainability results of an investment depend decisively on the system it is embedded in.”).

29 

Of course, such goals may sometimes be set by statute. For example, the 1972 Clean Water Act declared a policy that protected waters be fishable and swimmable by July 1, 1983. See 33 U.S.C. § 1251(a)(2).

30 

The 17 Goals, U.N. Dept of Econ. & Soc. Affs., https://sdgs.un.org/goals (last visited Jan. 23, 2023).

31 

Cass R. Sunstein, Cost-Benefit Analysis and the Environment, 115 Ethics 351, 382–83 (2005).

32 

For an influential discussion of “regulatory science,” see Sheila Jasanoff, The Fifth Branch: Science Advisors as Policymakers (1990).

33 

Lynton K. Caldwell, Environmental Quality as an Administrative Problem, 103 Annals Am. Acad. Pol. & Soc. Sci. 103, 113 (1972).

34 

Frank P. Grad, Environmental Law 13-1 (1971) (describing the Council on Environmental Quality).

35 

Nestor M. Davidson & Ethan J. Leib, Regleprudence—at OIRA and Beyond, 103 Geo. L. J. 259, 280 (2015).

36 

See Exec. Order No. 12,866, 58 Fed. Reg. 51735 § 4 (Sept. 30, 1993). Under President Biden, “OMB has recommended that agencies engage the public when developing their annual regulatory agendas.” The White House, supra note 9, at 8.

37 

See Spring 2023 Unified Agenda of Regulatory and Deregulatory Actions, Off. Info. & Regul. Affs., https://www.reginfo.gov/public/do/eAgendaMain (last visited Jan. 28, 2023).

38 

Exec. Order No. 12,866, 58 Fed. Reg. 51735 § 4.

39 

Id.

40 

This “ecological” view of democracy is of course contestable. Though I cannot defend it here, I hope the reader will find it sufficiently plausible to grant it to me.

41 

Samuel Bagg & Udit Bhatia, Intra-Party Democracy: A Functionalist Account, 30 J. Pol. Phil. 347, 350 (2022).

42 

Rahman, supra note 10, at 141 (defending the “forum” view).

43 

Nicholas Bagley, The Procedure Fetish, 118 Mich. L. Rev. 345, 377 (2019).

44 

Cf. Jeremy Waldron, Representative Lawmaking, 89 B.U. L. Rev. 335, 353 (2009) (“The people’s capacity for judgment is at stake when we look for a democratic mode of lawmaking, and if we are to respect that capacity, we must respect the forms, structures and processes that can house and frame it.”).

45 

For discussion of the “major questions” doctrine, see infra notes 78–79 and accompanying text.

46 

Cf. Jed Rubenfeld, Freedom and Time: A Theory of Constitutional Self-Government 11 (2001) (presenting the thesis that “democracy consists … in a people’s living out its own self-given political and legal commitments over time”).

47 

See Pierson, supra note 23, at 259.

48 

See Krahé, supra note 28, at 29 (discussing fiscal sustainability). For an analysis of the importance of the government’s reputation for policy efficacy, see Amy E. Lerman, Good Enough for Government Work: The Public Reputation Crisis in America (and What We Can Do to Fix It) (2019).

49 

See Robert J. Lempert, A New Decision Sciences for Complex Systems, 99 Proc. Natl Acad. Scis. 7309, 7309 (2002).

50 

For social trust, see, for example, Amaney Jamal & Irfan Nooruddin, The Democratic Utility of Trust: A Cross-National Analysis, 72 J. Pol. 45, 58 (2010) (concluding that “trust is nurtured and reinforced by existing political institutions, and citizens who are more confident in extant institutions, whether democratic or authoritarian, are more likely to be [generally] trusting”). For political trust, see, for example, Gabriela Catterberg & Alejandro Moreno, The Individual Bases of Political Trust: Trends in New and Established Democracies, 18 Intl J. Pub. Op. Rsch. 31, 45 (2006) (finding that “political trust depends strongly on performance”).

51 

Marlene Mauk, Disentangling an Elusive Relationship: How Democratic Value Orientations Affect Political Trust in Different Regimes, 73 Pol. Rsch. Q. 366, 372 (2020) (“[I]f citizens view the regime as very democratic, democratic value orientations increase their trust in the regime.”). Democratic theorists have offered a broader, though related argument: procedures equally respecting citizens’ claims provide assurance that “unwelcome” political outcomes are not “the sign of a malign will at work against you or your kind.” Philip Pettit, On the Peoples Terms: A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy 177 (2012).

52 

See, e.g., Olivier Bargain & Ulugbek Aminjonov, Trust and Compliance to Public Health Policies in Times of COVID-19, 192 J. Pub. Econ. 1, 13 (2020), https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jpubeco.2020.104316 (“Trust in governments is an important determinant of citizens’ compliance with public health policies, especially in times of crisis.”).

53 

Samuel DeCanio, Efficiency, Legitimacy, and the Administrative State, 38 Soc. Phil. & Pol. 198, 202 (2021). State-federal policy variation permits some comparisons, but “the political units used to generate the counterfactual … are not identical on all covariates except exposure to the policy ‘treatment.’ Thus, while comparisons can be employed to support specific causal claims, it is difficult to rule out confounding variables with the same level of certainty that is possible with actual scientific experiments.” Id. at 208.

54 

Id. at 207.

55 

Walters, supra note 10, at 9.

56 

Broadly speaking, my approach here is “realist” insofar as it aims to promote political accountability without seeking social transformation; I am concerned here with how elites do their jobs more than with empowering non-elite citizens. But my conception is not “minimalist” insofar as (1) I retain freedom and equality as normative lodestars even for elite reforms and (2) I pursue freedom and equality through mechanisms other than retrospective accountability through elections. For an insightful discussion of democratizing policy making from a different theoretical perspective, see K. Sabeel Rahman & Jocelyn Simonson, The Institutional Design of Community Control, 108 Cal. L. Rev. 101 (2020).

57 

Michael Sant’Ambrogio and Glen Staszewski offer a number of valuable granular suggestions for institutionalizing public participation in rule development. For example, drawing on current practice, they suggest that agencies prepare public-engagement plans. See Michael Sant’Ambrogio & Glen Staszewski Democratizing Rule Development, 98 Wash. U. L. Rev. 793, 833 (2021). The Office of Management and Budget (OMB) has also investigated an ambitious approach to “stakeholder engagement,” rightly concluding that “there is no one-size-fits-all approach.” Off. of Mgmt. & Budget, Study to Identify Methods to Assess Equity: Report to the President 32 (2021), https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-content/uploads/2021/08/OMB-Report-on-E013985-Implementation_508-Compliant-Secure-v1.1.pdf.

I focus here on the novel elements of my approach, setting aside some important details about how to implement “democratization.”

58 

See, e.g., Hélène Landemore, Open Democracy: Reinventing Popular Rule for the Twenty-First Century (2020); Ethan J. Leib, Deliberative Democracy in America (2004); Alexander A. Guerrero, Against Elections: The Lottocratic Alternative, 42 Phil. & Pub. Affs. 135 (2014).

59 

See Dimitra Landa & Ryan Pevnick, Is Random Selection a Cure for the Ills of Electoral Representation?, 29 J. Pol. Phil. 46, 46 (2021) (arguing that some sortition-based proposals “would likely exacerbate, rather than mitigate, the problems they seek to address”).

60 

Cf. Samuel Bagg, Sortition as Anti-Corruption, Am. J. Pol. Sci. (forthcoming), https://doi.org/10.1111/ajps.12704. Bagg emphasizes that citizen assemblies should be understood in terms of “sortition as anti-corruption” rather than of “sortition as representation.” My view is that in this context, “anti-corruption”—which I take to include vindicating the freedom and equality of each citizen—would likely be well-served by improving representation, and vice versa. In any case, I do not claim that citizen assemblies would perfectly represent the citizenry. Like Bagg, I think that goal is unachievable. Cf. Walters, supra note 10.

61 

Just as I do not argue for “sortition as representation,” neither do I argue for lottocratic bodies as promoting “the republican virtue of collective self-government” or reflecting “the Kantian claim that each citizen should be the author of his or her own laws.” Leib, supra note 58, at 10.

62 

Cf. Blake Emerson, Administrative Answers to “Major Questions,” 102 Minn. L. Rev. 2019, 2065 (2018) (describing the Progressive ideal of administrative agencies becoming “part and parcel of the process by which [political] purposes [are] identified” and hence having “a central role to play in the deliberative process, rather than [standing] completely outside politics as an efficient instrument for realizing democratic will”).

63 

See Jody Freeman & Jim Rossi, Agency Coordination in Shared Regulatory Space, 125 Harv. L. Rev. 1131, 1157–58 (2012).

64 

Cass Sunstein, The Office of Information and Regulatory Affairs: Myths and Realities, 126 Harv. L. Rev. 1838, 1840 (2013).

65 

Michael A. Livermore and Richard L. Revesz have offered a related argument, namely, that interagency coordination helps prevent regulatory capture. Michael A. Livermore & Richard L. Revesz, Regulatory Review, Capture, and Agency Inaction, 101 Geo. L. J. 1337, 1367–69 (2013).

66 

To see this, consider failures of interagency coordination: when one agency has excessive sway over policy, there is a prima facie cost to democracy, insofar as it renders ineffectual citizens’ prior commitments, as expressed through other agencies.

67 

Elena Kagan, Presidential Administration, 114 Harv. L. Rev. 2245 (2001).

68 

Emerson, supra note 62, at 2076; see also Blake Emerson & Jon D. Michaels, Abandoning Presidential Administration: A Civic Governance Agenda to Promote Democratic Equality and Guard Against Creeping Authoritarianism, 68 U.C.L.A. L. Rev. Discourse 104, 115–17 (2021).

69 

Jeremy Kessler & Charles Sabel, The Uncertain Future of Administrative Law, 150 Daedalus 188, 196 (2021).

70 

Id. at 202.

71 

To emphasize: I am not suggesting that the regulatory procedures I describe in this article should substitute for other democratizing reforms in general, or that they should substitute for strengthening congressional capacity in particular.

72 

Emerson, supra note 62, at 2083.

73 

Of course, scholars and others often justify other aspects of regulation-development in democratic terms.

74 

Sunstein, supra note 64, at 1869–70.

75 

Id. at 1843.

76 

These are not the only potentially relevant considerations. For example, regulators may also consider whether a given statute substantively advances democratic values and whether its enactment followed a particularly flawed (or sound) democratic process. None of this is to suggest that regulators should defy statutory mandates just because they are undemocratic. The point, rather, is that the relative democratic authority of a particular enactment should inform which additional measures, beyond the bare legal minimum, regulators should take in administering it.

77 

Blake Emerson, The Values of the Administrative State: A Reply to Seidenfeld, 119 Mich. L. Rev. Online 81, 87–88 (2021).

78 

West Virginia v. EPA, 142 S. Ct. 2487, 2609 (2022) (quoting Util. Air Reg. Grp. v. EPA, 573 U.S. 302, 324 (2014)).

79 

Id. at 2595 (quoting FDA v. Brown & Williamson Tobacco Corp., 529 U.S. 120, 159–60 (2000)).

80 

Adrian Vermeule, Deference and Due Process, 129 Harv. L. Rev. 1890, 1914 (2016).

81 

These caveats are also likely applicable to other features of the “democratic approach,” though I only mention them here.

82 

Sunstein, supra note 64, at 1841.

83 

Jacob Gersen & Adrian Vermeule, Thin Rationality Review, 114 Mich. L. Rev. 1355, 1403–04 (2016).

84 

The converse holds for line-agency staff.

85 

In this subpart, I present in the footnotes some detailed suggestions for operationalizing my ideas. I focus on the core arguments for my proposals in the main text.

86 

Jacob S. Hacker, Privatizing Risk Without Privatizing the Welfare State: The Hidden Politics of Social Policy Retrenchment in the United States, 98 Am. Pol. Sci. Rev. 243, 246 (2004).

87 

See Daniel J. Galvin & Jacob S. Hacker, The Political Effects of Policy Drift: Policy Stalemate and American Political Development, 34 Stud. Am. Pol. Dev. 216, 233–36 (2020).

88 

See id. at 224–27.

89 

See Elisabeth Ellis, Democracy as Constraint and Possibility for Environmental Action, in The Oxford Handbook of Environmental Political Theory 505, 509 (Teena Gabrielson et al. eds., 2016) (“Each demos must be free to make decisions as it sees fit, subject to the caveat … that democracy itself must continue to be possible. Thus in general democratic policies must be reversible.”).

90 

See generally Richard J. Lazarus, Super Wicked Problems and Climate Change: Restraining the Present to Liberate the Future, 94 Cornell L. Rev. 1153 (2009) (defending entrenchment of legislative climate policies).

91 

See Hacker, supra note 86, at 246 (defining “drift”).

92 

Others have noted the importance of designing climate policies that remain durable in the face of political change. See, e.g., Peter Howard & Michael A. Livermore, Sociopolitical Feedbacks and Climate Change, 43 Harv. Envt L. Rev. 119 (2019); Barry Rabe, The Durability of Carbon Cap-and-Trade Policy, 29 Governance 103 (2016); Ann E. Carlson & Robert W. Fri, Designing a Durable Energy Policy, 142 Daedalus 114 (2013); Kelly Levin et al., Overcoming the Tragedy of Super Wicked Problems: Constraining Our Future Selves to Ameliorate Global Change, 45 Poly Scis. 123 (2012); Lazarus, supra note 90. I build upon this work by focusing on regulatory review, rather than primarily on legislation; by shifting from climate change in particular to structural risks in general; and by integrating their arguments with the political-science literature on policy drift.

93 

Cf. Daryl Levinson & Benjamin I. Sachs, Political Entrenchment and Public Law, 125 Yale L. J. 400 (2015) (discussing functional entrenchment of public policy).

94 

Across various domains, scholars and policy makers have recently shown particular interest in what K. Sabeel Rahman calls “structuralist regulation”: policies intended “to mitigate problematic conduct not through direct enforcement on individual actors, but rather by altering the background social, economic, political structures to prophylactically prevent or reduce the incentives for and likelihood of those incidents.” K. Sabeel Rahman, Structuralist Regulation 6 (Spring 2023) (unpublished manuscript) (on file with the author). Consideration of such policies tends to make especially salient the political values at stake in a given policy domain. As Rahman has noted, many contemporary “movements for economic and racial justice … deploy a specifically structural language and frame for diagnosing the root causes of inequality and in the solutions they are offering.” Id. at 36. For this reason, “structuralist regulation” (in Rahman’s sense) may have particular appeal in addressing “structural risks” (in my sense).

95 

Under President Biden, OMB has examined a distinct but related approach to policy analysis: “equity assessment.” Insofar as “equity” is a component of both policy feedback and democratic feedback, such assessment could complement the methods I propose here. See Off. of Mgmt. & Budget, supra note 57, at 14–20.

96 

E. E. Schattschneider, Politics, Pressures and the Tariff 288 (1935). Public-policy scholar Barry Rabe has offered several questions that can helpfully orient policy-feedback and democratic-feedback analysis. They are (1) whether the policy is likely to continue to operate for at least a half-decade, with indications of political resilience beyond that; (2) whether the policy provides implementing agencies sufficient flexibility to adjust course once performance indicators emerge; and (3) whether the policy can produce sufficient benefits to build and sustain constituency support, especially against future political challenges. Rabe, The Durability of Carbon Cap-and-Trade Policy, supra note 92, at 138. These questions roughly correspond to the different timescales on which a policy can be democratically durable, from initial “stickiness” to longer-term “entrenchment” to possible “expansion.” Levin et al., supra note 92, at 138.

97 

To emphasize: I do not mean to suggest that regulation, let alone structural-risk regulation, can be made into an exact science. But policies already have profound political consequences. I hope only that these effects can become an object of administrators’ considerations, even if not of their knowledge.

98 

Generally speaking, significant policy change is more likely when an instrument (1) includes monitoring provisions, which help identify lapses in performance; (2) includes revision steps, which facilitate modification; and (3) is perceived as fungible. See Andrew Jordan & Elah Matt, Designing Policies That Intentionally Stick: Policy Feedback in a Changing Climate, 47 Poly Scis. 227, 237 (2014).

99 

For example, instruments may create constituencies with vested interests in preventing policy expansion, may facilitate policy expansion for one sub-population while hindering it for others, or may gain support from one subpopulation while losing support from another. See Levin et al., supra note 92, at 136.

100 

Positive policy feedback is more likely in cases involving (1) large fixed costs, which create high payoffs for further investments; (2) learning effects, in which knowledge gained leads to higher returns from a given policy; (3) coordination or network effects, where practices generate increasing returns as more agents adopt them; and (4) adaptive expectations, where agents’ expectations become self-fulfilling through explicit or tacit social coordination. See Paul Pierson, Politics in Time 24 (2004).

Negative policy feedback is more likely in cases where (1) policies impose immediate, concentrated costs on particular groups; (2) those disadvantaged by policies are powerful, well-organized, and highly motivated; (3) initial justifications for the policy were strongly contested or undermined by subsequent events; or (4) opponents effectively have no alternative but to mobilize against the policy. Andrew Jordan & Brendan Moore, Durable by Design? Policy Feedback in a Changing Climate 39 (2020).

101 

Id. at 13.

102 

Frances C. Moore et al., Determinants of Emissions Pathways in the Coupled Climate Social System, 603 Nature 103 (2022).

103 

Moore and her co-authors have also usefully recommended conducting targeted literature reviews to evaluate evidence for and against candidate feedback mechanisms. See id. at 104. Where existing research is inadequate to support policy-feedback analysis, regulators may also consider conducting original research to generate or test hypotheses. For example, public-opinion or sociological studies may suggest how information flows within a given policy domain, with important implications for which interpretive mechanisms might be most important. Cf. A. Abdulla et al., Limits to Deployment of Nuclear Power for Decarbonization: Insights from Public Opinion, 129 Energy Poly 1339 (2019).

104 

See generally Landemore, supra note 19 (defending rule of the many on epistemic grounds).

105 

Regulators may draw guidance concerning democracy’s meaning from sources including (1) federal statutes and regulations; (2) interagency consultation; (3) presidential priorities; (4) state and local statutes, ordinances, and regulations; (5) public contributions to systemic-goal-setting processes; and (6) scholarship in relevant academic disciplines, such as political philosophy, political science, and law.

106 

In conducting democratic-feedback analysis, regulatory reviewers may consider how a given policy may affect (1) citizens’ effective ability to participate individually and collectively in the political process; (2) the well-being and political status of groups already politically marginalized or otherwise disadvantaged; (3) the transmission of politically relevant information; (4) the stability of citizens’ political communities (e.g., through migration); (5) the distribution of wealth and income; (6) the stability of political institutions; (7) the responsiveness of those institutions to political majorities; or (8) the responsiveness of the proposed policy to political majorities. This list is intended only to be illustrative, not exhaustive.

107 

Serge Taylor, Making Democracies Think: The Environmental Impact Strategy of Administrative Reform (1984); see also generally Wendy Nelson Espeland, The Struggle for Water: Politics, Rationality, and Identity in the American Southwest (1998) (analyzing the political and social construction of “rationality”).

108 

See Sunstein, supra note 64, at 1873.

109 

Exec. Order 13,563, 76 Fed. Reg. 821 (Feb. 18, 2011).

110 

Gillian Metzger, Administrative Constitutionalism, 91 Tex. L. Rev. 1897, 1900 (2013); see also Davidson & Leib, supra note 35 (describing the development of an internal, evolving rule of law within OIRA).

111 

For examples and further discussion of this approach, see, for example, Ian Shapiro, Politics Against Domination (2016); Samuel Bagg, The Power of the Multitude: Answering Epistemic Challenges to Democracy, 112 Am. Pol. Sci. Rev. 891 (2018).

112 

See, e.g., Emerson, supra note 62 (defending judicial solicitude for decisions made through more democratic procedures); Nina A. Mendelson, Disclosing “Political” Oversight of Agency Decision Making, 108 Mich. L. Rev. 1127, 1129–30 (2010) (collecting sources at an earlier phase of the debate).

113 

Dep’t of Com. v. New York, 139 S. Ct. 2551, 2573 (2019) (quoting Sierra Club v. Costle, 657 F.2d 298 (D.C. Cir. 1981)).

114 

Dep’t of Homeland Sec. v. Regents of the Univ. of Cal., 140 S. Ct. 1891 (2020).

115 

Benjamin Eidelson, Reasoned Explanation and Political Accountability in the Roberts Court, 130 Yale L. J. 1748, 1752–53 (2021).

116 

Considerations of democratic durability also find support in longstanding administrative-law principles. Under Motor Vehicle Mfrs. Ass’n of U.S. v. State Farm Mut. Auto. Ins. Co., 463 U.S. 29, 56 (1983), the arbitrary-and-capricious standard permits administrators to consider the likely “public reaction” to their decisions, provided that they offer explanations for their assessments. The review procedures I propose here would facilitate the development of reasons that could be offered in support of particular structural-risk regulations. In that respect, they would buttress administrative decisions against judicial review.

One might object that my proposals are qualitatively different, in two related respects. First, they concern not the first-order efficacy of a given policy but rather its second-order resistance to certain changes, and second, they represent an effort to entrench policies against “[a] change in administration brought about by the people casting their votes.” Id. at 59 (Rehnquist, J., concurring in part). The first of these relies upon an intuitive distinction between “first-order” and “second-order” effects that does not withstand scrutiny. Suppose some members of the public object to a certain requirement in a promulgated rule (concerning, for example, automotive safety) and therefore refuse to adhere to that requirement. That consequence results from the interaction of the rule with existing social practice. It is already a “second-order” effect, even if the results seem in some sense more “proximate” than the implications of that public reaction for the political longevity of the rule. There is no reason to impose (and no legal basis for imposing) a “proximate cause” requirement limiting considerations of democratic durability. Indeed, such a requirement would likely undermine structural-risk regulation altogether, even if it did not comport with my suggested approach.

The second distinction overlooks the distinctly democratic ambitions of my proposals. In effect, the worry is that considering policy durability would amount to an objectionable form of entrenchment. But while structural-risk regulations should ideally generate their own political support, they should not foreclose deliberate political change consistent with citizens’ freedom and equality (and with existing law). To be sure, in any particular case, one might object that administrators have not struck an appropriate balance between policy durability and democratic values and therefore wrongly entrenched their favored policies. But this would not support a normative objection to the general practice of considering democratic durability unless one is prepared to reject all efforts to entrench certain policies. And that would be a dubious task, given that all policies operate over time (and even systemically) to greater or lesser degrees. Moreover, judicial review along these lines may be limited by Vermont Yankee Nuclear Power Corp. v. Nat. Res. Def. Council, Inc., 435 U.S. 519 (1978). In particular, so long as administrators complied with all relevant statutory law, courts lack authority to require additional administrative procedures—including those a court might think more democratic.

I thank Ben Eidelson for raising these concerns, though the formulations of them here are my own.

117 

Cf. Jordan & Matt, Designing Policies that Intentionally Stick, supra note 98, at 234 (suggesting mechanisms for promoting flexibility in policy design).

118 

Jan-Werner Müller, Democracy Rules 94 (2021).

119 

See R. Henry Weaver & Douglas A. Kysar, Courting Disaster: Climate Change and the Adjudication of Catastrophe, 93 Notre Dame L. Rev. 295, 298–300 (2017). But cf. Tom Ginsburg & Mila Versteeg, The Bound Executive: Emergency Powers During the Pandemic, 19 Intl J. Const. L. 1498 (2021) (arguing that the COVID-19 pandemic did not lead to an “unbound executive”).

120 

Marta Simonici, Regulating Catastrophic Risks by Standards, 2 Eur. J. Risk Regul. 37, 45 (2011). Designing regulatory triggers involves answering at least three principal questions: (1) by reference to what variables should thresholds be set? (2) at what levels should thresholds be set? and (3) what regulatory responses are appropriate at each threshold?

Choosing variables for thresholds is closely linked to setting systemic goals. In many cases, the goal-setting process may indicate what information is most relevant to particular structural-risk regulations. For example, if regulators are considering climate-related regulations, they might learn more through goal setting about the possible consequences of different atmospheric concentrations of carbon dioxide. On this basis, they may determine that atmospheric carbon dioxide concentrations provide an appropriate variable in which to set “thresholds.” In some cases, however, it may be appropriate to set thresholds in terms of a proxy variable—for example, if the underlying variable of interest is difficult to measure with precision.

Regulators should justify all choices regarding threshold placement in terms of systemic objectives. For example, if they have previously determined that some level of climate change–related risk is unacceptable, they should calibrate thresholds to mitigate that risk. Regulators should also generally create “alarms” for when risk is increasing so as to provide an adequate margin of safety. In setting alarm thresholds, they should consider both the expected benefits and the expected costs (if any) of thresholds. For example, thresholds set too low may inappropriately divert resources from other regulatory initiatives or may lead to the imposition of unjustifiably burdensome regulations. Regulators need not set all thresholds in terms of the same variables. In some cases, it may be appropriate to rely upon a suite of alarms.

Choices among regulatory responses to each threshold are effectively choices among new (conditional) policies, and regulators should treat them as such. To the extent possible, they should subject these decisions to the same review procedures applicable to the initially enforceable regulatory regime. When a proposed regulatory regime includes both rules immediately enforceable after their promulgation and rules enforceable only upon certain “triggers,” regulators should not assume that the two must be similar. For example, an environmental regulation may require only certain public disclosures in the first instance but then impose pollution standards if some “threshold of alarm” is reached.

“Thresholds of alarm” may be complemented by ongoing monitoring and review of the regulatory scheme. Continuous observation can promote flexibility if new information suggests the inadequacy of a previously chosen threshold. Regulators should therefore consider whether a proposed regulation may be designed to encourage monitoring. These thresholds should themselves be subject to policy-feedback and democratic-feedback analysis.

121 

Johan Rockström et al., Planetary Boundaries: Exploring the Safe Operating Space for Humanity, 14 Ecology & Socy 31 (2009).

122 

This example will be familiar from New York v. United States, 505 U.S. 144, 153 (1992), in which the Court struck down the take-title provision on federalism grounds not relevant here.

123 

Michael A. Livermore & Richard L. Revesz, Retaking Rationality 15 (2008).

124 

Edward H. Stiglitz, Delegating for Trust, 166 U. Pa. L. Rev. 633, 685 (2018).

125 

Id. at 685 n.250 (quoting A.R. Prest & R. Turvey, Cost–Benefit Analysis: A Survey, 75 Econ. J. 683, 685 (1965)).

126 

Susan Rose-Ackerman, Putting Cost-Benefit Analysis in Its Place, 65 U. Miami L. Rev. 335, 354 (2011).

127 

Of course, cost–benefit analysis has been subject to wide-ranging debate. To the extent that other criticisms are persuasive in “ordinary” cases, they still apply here.

128 

Rose-Ackerman, supra note 126, at 354; cf. Sunstein, supra note 31, at 383–84 (defending an “Anti-Catastrophe Principle”).

129 

See Matthew D. Adler & Eric A. Posner, Rethinking Cost–Benefit Analysis, 109 Yale L. J. 165, 167–68 (1999) (“A decision procedure is a method for achieving desirable results, and some decision procedures are more accurate or less costly than others.”).

130 

Cf. Howard & Livermore, supra note 92 (showing the relevance of sociopolitical feedbacks to reducing greenhouse-gas emissions).

131 

Amartya Sen, The Discipline of Cost–Benefit Analysis, 29 J. Legal Studs. 931, 951 (2000).

132 

Id. at 949; cf. Jonathan S. Masur & Eric A. Posner, Climate Regulation and the Limits of Cost–Benefit Analysis, 99 Cal. L. Rev. 1557, 1596–97 (2011) (offering other examples of “principally normative, political and institutional questions” that frustrate cost–benefit analysis). These concerns suggest that cost–benefit analysis may indeed sometimes be altogether inappropriate, even if those cases cannot easily be specified in advance.

133 

See, e.g., Sunstein, supra note 31, at 355 (“Human beings are citizens, not merely consumers, and their consumption choices, as measured by [willingness to pay], might be trumped by their reflective judgments as citizens.”).

134 

See, e.g., Arnaud Goussebaïle, Democratic Climate Policies with Overlapping Generations (Oct. 6, 2022) (unpublished manuscript), https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cf\m?abstract_id=4239532.

135 

Information and Regulatory Affairs, The White House, https://www.whitehouse.gov/omb/information-regulatory-affairs/ (last visited Jan. 23, 2023).

136 

For a foundational discussion of “state capacity” as a constraint upon policy reform, see Theda Skocpol & Kenneth Finegold, State Capacity and Economic Intervention in the Early New Deal, 97 Pol. Sci. Q. 255 (1982). For a valuable analysis of the personnel reforms necessary to support certain democratizing reforms, see K. Sabeel Rahman & Hollie Russon Gilman, Civic Power: Rebuilding Democracy in an Era of Crisis ch. 5 (2019).

137 

Memorandum on Modernizing Regulatory Review, 86 Fed. Reg., at 7224.

138 

Jacob S. Hacker, Book Review, 20 Perspectives on Pol. 1449, 1450 (2022). Hacker briefly wonders what a “political style of thinking” about public policy “might entail.” Id. at 1450. This article, which has drawn substantially on Hacker’s work, may be read as an attempt at an answer.

139 

See, e.g., Gregory A. Huber, The Craft of Bureaucratic Neutrality: Interests and Influence in Governmental Regulation of Occupational Safety (2007) (examining bureaucrats’ cultivation of “strategic neutrality” to manage political pressures); Daniel Carpenter, The Forging of Bureaucratic Autonomy: Reputations, Networks, and Policy Innovation in Executive Agencies, 1862–1928 (2001) (studying the long-term development of agency reputation as a precondition for political autonomy).

140 

James Kwak, Cultural Capture and the Financial Crisis, in Preventing Regulatory Capture: Special Interest Influence and How to Limit It 71, 76 (Daniel Carpenter & David A. Moss eds., 2014).

141 

Id. at 79; see also Jeremy K. Kessler, Illiberalism and Administrative Government, in Law and Illiberalism 62, 71–72 (Martha Merrill Umphrey et al. eds., 2022) (discussing the significance of the socioeconomic composition of the administrative corps); Jeremy K. Kessler, The Struggle for Administrative Legitimacy, 129 Harv. L. Rev. 718 (2016) (book review) (suggesting that the “rule of lawyers” within the administrative state has proven a tenuous basis for its legitimation).

142 

I thank Paul Frymer for raising this concern.

143 

See Elizabeth Popp Berman, Thinking Like an Economist: How Efficiency Replaced Equality in U.S. Public Policy 3 (2022).

144 

Bridget C. E. Dooling, An Overview of Biden’s First Regulatory Year, Brookings (Jan. 20, 2022), https://www.brookings.edu/blog/up-front/2022/01/20/an-overview-of-bidens-first-regulatory-year/.

145 

The Administration seems to have recognized this, too. See supra note 9.

146 

See Berman, supra note 143, 62–66 (describing the diffusion of the “economic style” in the 1960s and 70s through graduate programs in public policy); Skocpol & Finegold, supra note 136, at 273–74 (discussing the importance of land-grant colleges to the U.S. Department of Agriculture in the late nineteenth century).

147 

Cf. Steven M. Teles, The Rise of the Conservative Legal Movement: The Battle for the Control of Law (2008) (examining the role of such institutions among conservative lawyers).

148 

For example, turning to these institutions would do little to shift power from the “self-reproducing professional class” that now leads the administrative state. The class composition of agencies is largely a function of secular political developments. See Kessler, supra note 141, at 72.

149 

See generally Bagley, supra note 43 (criticizing the view that administrative ills can reliably be cured through additional procedural requirements).

150 

For an early and influential discussion of “ossification,” see Thomas O. McGarity, Some Thoughts on “Deossifying” the Rulemaking Process, 41 Duke L. J. 1385 (1992).

151 

Gillian E. Metzger, The Supreme Court, 2016 Term: Foreword: 1930s Redux: The Administrative State Under Siege, 131 Harv. L. Rev. 1, 4 (2017).

152 

See Emerson, supra note 62, at 2088.

153 

See Nicholas Bagley & Richard L. Revesz, Centralized Oversight of the Regulatory State, 106 Colum. L. Rev. 1260, 1274–80 (2006) (criticizing OIRA’s historical failure to engage in such review).

154 

58 Fed. Reg. 51,735 § 6(a)(3)(A).

155 

Michael A. Livermore & Richard L. Revesz, Reviving Rationality: Saving Cost-Benefit Analysis for the Sake of the Environment and Our Health 27 (2020).

156 

Cf. Bagley, supra note 43, at 349 (setting out the thesis that procedural requirements in administrative law “may exacerbate the very problems [they] aim[] to address”).

157 

See generally Bagley & Revesz, supra note 153.

158 

See supra notes 57–62 and accompanying text.

159 

See supra Part II.B.

160 

See supra notes 99–100 and accompanying text.

161 

Walters, supra note 10, at 9.

162 

For the beginnings of my own answer to this question, see note 22 supra.

Author notes

*

Ph.D. candidate (politics), Princeton University; J.D., Yale Law School. For generous written comments, the author thanks Blake Emerson, Joey Fishkin, David Froomkin, Paul Frymer, Andrew Hahm, Jeremy Kessler, Ethan Leib, Ben Lempert, Martha Minow, Sam Moyn, Sabeel Rahman, Bo Seo, Dan Walters, and John Witt. For helpful discussion, he thanks Simmi Dhillon, Ben Eidelson, Martin Flaherty, Andrew Hahm, Ben Lempert, Jenne O’Brien, and workshop participants at Princeton, including Haris Durrani, Martin Flaherty, Dirk Hartog, Brian Highsmith, Tristan Hughes, and Karen Sokol.

This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License, which permits you to copy and redistribute in any medium or format, for non-commercial use only, provided that the original work is not remixed, transformed, or built upon, and that appropriate credit to the original source is given. For a full description of the license, please visit https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/legalcode.