When a monograph entitled After Misogyny dropped in 2023, readers would be forgiven for expecting a very different book than the one Professor Julie Suk gave us.1 “After” suggests a new phase of gender relations in a long history of sexism—and a book entitled After Misogyny could be introducing yet another wave in the many waves of feminism.2 One could imagine at least three different books on the state of sex and the law that could be written at this moment.

First would be the progress narrative. In the last five years, women occupied the number two3 and number three4 spots in the federal government for the first time in history and a woman nearly occupied the highest office in the land.5 We have seated four women on the Supreme Court.6 The #MeToo movement raised women’s voices in protest against sexual assault and harassment.7 A recent book has catalogued the many ways in which women are outpacing men, especially in education and employment.8 On this view, women have caught up with men, we are living in a post-gender America, and we are already (largely) after misogyny.

Second would be the backlash narrative. Nearly as dominant a frame for understanding the trajectory of feminism as waves flowing in and out like the tides is the idea of backlash, of feminism ping-ponging between periods of widespread acceptance and reactionary retrenchment.9 Numerous commentators have suggested that we are in a period of feminist backlash against the moments of progress or near progress10 cited above.11 We can see this first and foremost in the Dobbs decision, which overturned a half-century regime of a constitutional right to abortion;12 in the support for a former President who bragged about assaulting women and who was held civilly liable for doing so;13 and in the “manosphere,” where popular commentators like Jordan Peterson and Andrew Tate spew antifeminist venom,14 to name just a few examples. While backlash isn’t new, what’s different today is how openly it is practiced, with misogynists “tak[ing] the gloves off and pursuing a scorched-earth campaign against women’s most fundamental rights.”15

Third would be the chaos narrative. In the almost decade since Time magazine proclaimed a “transgender tipping point,”16 questions of what it means to be a woman have reverberated from the headlines of major publications17 to state legislatures across the nation18 and even to the halls of Congress, where the most recent Supreme Court confirmation hearings featured a question to Justice Ketanji Brown Jackson about “what makes a woman.”19 There is now a pitched battle, confirmed by a daily drumbeat of news on the competing laws and court decisions defining sex in this new environment, between those who view sex as a matter of gender identity and those who view sex in traditional biological terms.20 In other words, we are at a moment of intense contestation over the question of what sex even is.

Suk has written none of these books. Instead, Suk, one of the country’s foremost experts on the law of sex equality in the United States and abroad,21 has focused on how the law maintains misogynistic gender relations, even after formally unequal laws have been eradicated, and how we might go about changing this. “Misogyny, this book argues, is th[e] aftermath of patriarchy.”22 America was once under a regime of legal patriarchy, where the law of coverture granted male heads of household control over property and authority over children and denied women independent legal personhood.23 Between the mid-nineteenth and late twentieth centuries, these rules were replaced with a regime of formal legal equality. As Suk argues, despite “a legal and social order that officially embraces gender equality rather than patriarchy,” a system of misogyny has remained, with a legal edifice premised on women “sacrific[ing] their own well-being for the benefit of husbands, children, and other family members.”24

Suk begins by detailing the evolution of constitutional sex equality law in the United States, highlighting a dynamic of what Professor Reva Siegel has called “preservation through transformation”:25 the more things change, the more they stay the same. Suk observes how decisions striking down sex-based rules in the name of equality might instead result in furthering misogyny. For example, the Court’s 1976 ruling in Craig v. Boren26 holding that boys must be granted the same access to weak beer as girls also brings with it “the potential to nourish spaces of toxic masculinity.”27 In contrast to the anti-stereotyping vision of the Court’s equal protection doctrine,28 Suk’s is a feminism that wants to take account of sex difference and locates some of the law’s misogynistic tendencies in its failure to do so.29

For Suk, the “the core problem of misogyny … is taking too much from women.”30 She fleshes out the wrong of misogyny by way of analogy to the legal doctrines of unjust enrichment and abuse of right, explaining how misogyny is enacted by men’s over-entitlement and over-empowerment at the expense of women. On this view, women’s subordination stems from “organizing society around men’s entitlement to the value created by women, especially women’s unique and disproportionate contributions to human reproduction—both biological and social.”31

While borrowing from the theoretical underpinnings of private law doctrines, Suk makes clear that her purpose is broader than redistribution within the family and instead is for a “[l]aw and public policy” with a “restitutive approach to the benefits conferred on men and on society as a whole by women’s sacrifices.”32 She rereads Prohibition as a feminist movement to do just that, by using “constitutional change to reset the power of institutions and industries.”33 And she powerfully applies these insights to the critical and never more timely issue of abortion, explaining that “[t]o get a better handle on the real misogyny of banning abortion,” we need to see it as “government underreach, not government overreach.”34 As a number of other countries do, the state should take on responsibility for unwanted pregnancy to ameliorate the burdens it imposes on women.35

Much of After Misogyny is about the politics of misogyny rather than its legal doctrines. Suk locates the root of misogyny in a battle of the sexes—in “men’s sense of entitlement to women’s sacrifices” and the outsize power of men in leadership positions to enforce this entitlement.36 By so squarely representing misogyny as a matter of “us vs. them,” a book like this one asks its readers (and reviewers) to consider the status of gender relations and what it means to think of women (and men) as distinct political classes. This review takes up After Misogyny’s invitation to take stock of gender relations in America at a time when we might understandably be confused as to whether we are in a moment of progress, backlash, or chaos.

The first part of this review focuses on how Americans perceive (or do not perceive) the sort of misogyny that is at the center of Suk’s book. Suk largely assumes rather than proves the ongoing ubiquity of misogyny in law. Yet she does so at a time when readers might need a little more convincing. While the right never accepted the notion of women as a subordinated class,37 this was once a mainstay of the left.38 This view appears to be losing its grip, with multiple indications of the left’s uncertainty about the underlying fact of women’s disadvantage. This part considers the perception that we are after misogyny: that we as a society—including those on the left—no longer think of women as a political class facing subordination. If a law of misogyny persists but we no longer see it, it will be all the more difficult to combat.

To address misogyny, we have to get to its source. The second part of this review turns to the cause of misogyny. Taking for granted Suk’s definition of misogynistic laws and policies and focusing primarily on care and abortion, as Suk does, I question Suk’s causal story—that these laws are a result of men oppressing women—and instead highlight partisan divides and societal ambivalence about the proper roles of government, women, and mothers.

The third part of this review turns to Suk’s proposals for combatting misogyny. Much of Suk’s focus is on empowering women: if men are the problem, women are the solution. But if the causal story behind misogyny is more complicated than a battle of the sexes, so too is the remedy. I discuss how putting women in positions of power will not lead to empowering women and explore some alternative paths.

Suk presents a totalizing view of sex as a form of social organization with great explanatory power for relative positions in society: “Misogyny is the set of practices that keep women down in order to keep everyone and everything else up.”39 Suk’s rendition of misogyny shares a flavor of radical feminism, with the world divided up between men and women.40 In Suk’s world, women giveth and men taketh away: “Men, and the society founded and framed to meet their needs, derive irreplaceable benefits from women when women bear the enormous burdens of biological and social reproduction.”41 While Suk discusses intersectionality within the class of women,42 she does not address how men are not a monolithic class.

Suk’s book arrives at a time when whatever societal agreement there ever was about women’s disadvantage relative to men shows signs of unraveling. There has long been dissension about this on the right,43 but what is noteworthy are the indications that the left, and especially its youngest members, no longer share Suk’s view of misogyny.44 This part looks at the (still modest) evidence of this shift to show how Suk might have more work to do to establish her central claim of misogyny, even among her fellow lefties.

A recent New York Times op-ed by columnist Michelle Goldberg catalogues indicators of the decline of feminist identification.45 Last year, the left-wing literary journal The Drift published a series of essays around the notion that “feminism is in trouble,” especially among young people.46 One of the editors noted: “We’re quite alarmed to see that the people around us, who are our age, are by and large quite disaffected and maybe considered themselves feminists five years ago, but now don’t want to anymore.”47

Goldberg cites research that backs up this anecdotal telling from a 2022 poll of 1,500 Americans asking questions about the state of sex in society.48 The poll asked whether “feminism has done more harm than good.”49 Not surprisingly, a majority of Republicans agreed that “feminism has done more harm than good.”50 What is more striking is the substantial numbers of young Democrats (under fifty years old)—46% of young men and 23% of young women—who shared this view.51 Note that as compared with the 46% of young Democratic men who agreed, only 4% of older Democratic men did.52 Even among Democratic women, nearly a quarter of those under age fifty thought feminism was harmful, as compared with only 10% of those fifty and older.53 While the groups most aligned with feminism’s harmful impact were young Republican men (62%) and women (52%),54 the age effect can outstrip the gender and partisan effects: among Democrats, older men (4%) held a less negative view of feminism than younger women (23%), and among men, older Republicans (42%) are less skeptical of feminism than younger Democrats (46%).55

Polling on men’s roles in society echo the concern about a women-focused politics on the left, especially among younger Americans. A majority of Republicans polled agree that “[m]en should be respected and valued more in our society.”56 The number of younger Democrats who joined them was substantial, with younger Democratic women (35%) agreeing more than older Democratic women (27%) and younger Democratic men (60%) agreeing more than older Democratic men (28%).57 Among Democrats, younger women (35%) are more concerned with the state of men than older men (28%) are.58

Beyond these numbers, the notion that being a woman is necessarily a subordinated identity is being called into question, especially with regard to white women. Since 2020, a deluge of books with titles like The Trouble with White Women and What’s Up with White Women have appeared.59 In a 2019 conversation between Brown University economics professor Glenn Loury and author Meghan Daum about Daum’s book on the “culture wars,” Loury noted that it would be inappropriate for a man to critique a feminist perspective. Daum replied, “Well, increasingly, I think white women are the new white men here. So I’m not sure I can even say anything.”60 For good measure, Loury responds: “White, cisgender, heterosexual woman, not to get too personal.”61 A pop icon no less than Taylor Swift provides another example. Last year, when author and model Emily Ratajkowski called out sexism against Swift, she explained that Swift is “another example of a woman who has been faced with such blatant misogyny and sexism,” but the public doesn’t see it “because she’s powerful and successful, and also she’s white.”62

Consider the “Karen” as further evidence of the breakdown of assumptions of sexism. While the Karen meme had been kicking around the internet for years (and for many decades prior as “Miss Anne”), it breathed new life in the spring of 2020. Weeks into the COVID-19 lockdown, a white woman was nicknamed the “Central Park Karen” after she called the police on a Black man who asked her to comply with the park’s leashing requirement, invoking his race during the call.63 A video of the incident went viral, sparking a national discourse about the dangers of Black people being falsely accused as well as a deluge of essays about white women’s exercise of racial privilege.64 Some writers called out the sexism involved in the Karen meme, which placed a needed focus on racism wrought by white women but did so by relying on sex stereotypes about assertive women while simultaneously letting white men off the hook.65 Others shot down notions of sexism and instead urged that the Karen meme be viewed as “part of a long tradition to use humor to try to cope with the realities of white privilege and anti-blackness.”66

This may be rehashing an old debate that has migrated from the pages of the Yale Law Journal to the pages of the New York Times. In a 1991 essay prefiguring the notion of the white woman as the new white man, Catharine MacKinnon argued against the stereotype of the white woman as Karen—“effete, pampered, privileged, protected, flighty, and self-indulgent”—and “not poor, not battered, not raped (not really), not molested as a child, not pregnant as a teenager, not prostituted, not coerced into pornography, not a welfare mother and not economically exploited.”67 Her point was that sexism is powerful, and even whiteness does not guard against it. A response to MacKinnon by the Yale Collective on Women of Color took issue with MacKinnon’s essentializing—her “universal concept of womanhood”—that failed to recognize how race and other identities intersected with and, yes, modified women’s experiences.68 But this exchange differed in one important respect from the one we see today: even MacKinnon’s critics agreed that “any social privilege that is accessed by women is degraded in relation to that of men.”69 Thirty years later, the left no longer seems to view women as universally oppressed by virtue of their sex alone.

The decline of sex as a salient category can be felt close to home, in legal academia. Professor David Schleicher has suggested that the focus on structural bias against women has declined in law schools.70 Consider one example: the study of student experiences by sex has been a staple of legal academia for over three decades.71 Professor Schleicher notes that “it’s a little hard to imagine that happening right at this moment.”72 The data largely back him up, with the last study of this kind having been initiated before 2020.73 Yale Law Women conducted its first such study in 2002 and did an update ten years later in 2012.74 No update was undertaken in 2022. Citations to MacKinnon, the most-cited feminist legal scholar and one of the most-cited legal scholars overall, are down.75 Berkeley Law recently added a course requirement for graduation to promote learning on diversity, equity, and inclusion that can be fulfilled only by taking a class on race, not gender (or any other marginalized identity).76

For one additional data point, compare the most recent volumes of the Harvard Law Review, volumes 135 and 136 (2022–23), and those published thirty years ago, volumes 105 and 106 (1992–93). Each of the older volumes had one major article focused on women’s subordination,77 as well as several book reviews,78 notes,79 and case comments80 so focused. These numbers do not include the many pieces related to gender inequality on topics ranging from family law81 to rape law82 to pornography83 to domestic violence84 to LGBTQ rights.85 Though the recent volumes contain a few pieces on topics related to sex and gender—abortion,86 family law,87 and LGBTQ rights88—there are no pieces focused exclusively or primarily on women, sex, or gender, even with the Dobbs decision arriving in their midst.89

This review posits but does not claim to prove a decline in feminist or woman-focused orientation on the left. The methodology is admittedly loose, and the boundaries are intentionally fuzzy—for example, the time frame, scope, domain, or degree of any such shift. Exceptions and countervailing forces are readily available. Extensive media coverage of the Dobbs decision90 and the #MeToo movement91 have brought plenty of focus on women as a political class. Richard Reeves, the author of a recent book raising concerns about boys and men, noted that he was warned not to write it because “[i]n the current political climate, highlighting the problems of boys and men is seen as a perilous undertaking.”92 Notwithstanding the tentative nature of the claims here, this review suggests three forces that might be at work in a decline in women-centered orientation on the left: (1) the shifting positions of women relative to men, especially in education and employment; (2) the rise of other identity-based movements on the left, namely racial justice and transgender rights;93 and (3) the depoliticized nature of so-called “pop” feminism.

First, “the end of men” has been prophesied for decades,94 first from the right95 and then from the left.96 While earlier attempts heralding the end of men and the rise of women have been roundly criticized97 and substantially debunked,98 no longer is the story a simple zero-sum game of men losing and women winning. Reeves’s book, Of Men and Boys,99 and other recent work100 detail various declines among men101 while retaining awareness of women’s struggles and intersectionality with race and class. A few facts that Reeves reports are rightly attention-grabbing: for every one hundred bachelor’s degrees awarded to women, seventy-four are awarded to men.102 This gender gap in college degrees is larger now than in the 1970s but favors women rather than men.103 Most men’s wages are lower today than they were in 1979, while women’s wages have gone in the opposite direction.104

We can understand these shifts as gender intersecting with changes in the economy and bedrock institutions, such as schools. An economy once dominated by manufacturing is now overflowing with service jobs, and perhaps schools have come to reward the traits favored by such an economy, which girls tend to possess more than boys.105 These education and labor market gaps are particularly acute for Black boys and men.106 It was always the case that women as a class, while subordinated, were not viewed in a uniformly negative way.107 Rather, they were stereotyped as different than men in ways that society tended to value less.108 In our current world, some stereotypically feminine traits are simply worth more.

But this is not to suggest a simple reversal of the fates of men and women. We see the continuing impact of gender expectations in ways that can both help and hinder girls and women. While girls are outpacing boys at university, they are still underrepresented among STEM graduates.109 And, as Suk emphasizes, because women continue to bear the lion’s share of caregiving responsibilities, they still earn less than men110 and remain seriously underrepresented in the upper echelons of politics, business, and law,111 notwithstanding their advances in education. For women without college degrees, the future may look just as bleak as it does for their male counterparts.112

We might use the gendered labor impact of caregiving to understand the data on feminist identification discussed earlier, and particularly the fact that younger women are less likely to be fans of feminism.113 The data are ambiguous as to whether this is an age effect or a cohort effect. In other words, will younger women increase their feminist identification as they age, or will this cohort retain their views? The wage gap data could indicate that it’s the former.114 It turns out that the wage gap does not come into play until around age thirty, when people have kids.115 Young women today who have not started families have not yet been exposed to the factor imposing the greatest gendered impact on their work and might sing a different tune about feminism when they are. If so, feminist orientation is less about cohort effects and more about age and family status. If a conservative is a liberal who’s been mugged,116 perhaps a feminist is a woman who’s had a kid.117

In light of the ways that men who are not at the top are struggling, readers of After Misogyny might wonder whether the class of men dominates the class of women or, rather, society and the state fail to value stereotypically feminine virtues, such as care, regardless of who manifests them, a topic to which I will return.118 Men of course have no monopoly on exploitation. With so many parents in the labor force, someone has to take care of the kids. This labor continues to be done primarily by women, disproportionately low-wage women of color, especially immigrants, and often women with fewer legal protections, for the benefit not only of men but also of women.119 Moreover, gender expectations are harmful not only to women but also to men. Men can’t have it all either.120 Some men might want to do more care.121 Gender expectations pull women toward care and away from work while exerting the opposite pressures on men. And when men act “like women”—for example, when men seek workplace accommodations for caregiving—they too experience retaliation by their employers.122 In other words, the picture of gender relations today is hard to boil down to a simple story of misogyny.

Second, the left’s reduced focus on women might stem from an increased focus on other subordinated identities. In the wake of the killing of Trayvon Martin by George Zimmerman in 2012 and Michael Brown by Darren Wilson in 2014, the Black Lives Matter movement was born.123 These killings sparked a wave of protests and the ignition of the Movement for Black Lives aimed at combatting racism in policing and the criminal justice system.124 Among other changes, Black Lives Matter helped to make these forms of institutionalized racism more visible, both by “normalizing the filming of Black pain at the hand of individuals sworn to treat everyone equally” and with policy changes, such as routine use of body-worn cameras by police.125

There is evidence that Black Lives Matter shifted public discourse and opinion on race and racism.126 A Pew Study conducted in 2017 found that the proportion of Americans who see racism as a “big problem” in society had risen substantially since the advent of the movement,127 with the number of Americans who agreed with this statement jumping from 28% in 2011 to 50% in 2015 to 58% in 2017.128 The impact was even more dramatic on the left, with about three-quarters of Democrats seeing racism as a major issue.129 In this period, far more people ranked racial justice (56%) as an important political priority, as compared to paid leave (35%), an issue traditionally associated with gender equality.130 In fact, paid leave was ranked at the very bottom of a list of twenty-one policy items.131

Attention to transgender and nonbinary identity has also exploded.132 Since Time announced the arrival of a “transgender tipping point” in 2014,133 the increase in visibility of transgender people and themes in media and culture, along with accompanying policy changes, have been stunning.134 In response, the right has made combatting transgender rights the core plank of its anti-woke platform, with dozens of laws passed in recent years limiting transgender rights around bathroom use, athletic participation, medical care, and more.135 By contrast, the left, and especially its youngest members, have embraced transgender rights,136 with increasing numbers not only supporting transgender rights but identifying as transgender.137

The notion that the left’s focus on racial justice and transgender rights has reduced its attention to women’s inequality relies on a zero-sum model of activism, where energy toward one cause subtracts from another. It is not clear that activism works this way. On the one hand, activism is probably a scarce resource. On the other hand, activism for various causes may operate synergistically, so that action for one cause may increase action for another. And forces behind various causes may join together to support each other. The limited resource here might be not activism but our own cognition. It might be hard for people to hold two seemingly opposing ideas in their mind: that women are both the oppressors and the oppressed.

But it’s not only that fights for racial justice or transgender rights have shifted the focus away from feminism or women. In the public imagination, these battles have sometimes made women the enemy and, in the process, divided women on the left.138 Return to Karen. This meme places the blame for racism squarely on women, even though historically men have been the biggest transgressors of the rights of people of color.139 So too with transgender rights. Pamela Paul of the New York Times has written: “Consider that in the real world, most violence against trans men and women is committed by men but, in the online world and in the academy, most of the ire at those who balk at this new gender ideology seems to be directed at women.”140 Scapegoating is perhaps another tool of misogyny.

Third, it has been suggested that our current period of feminist retrenchment might be understood as a backlash,141 but one might ask: “Backlash to what?”142 Hostile reactions to feminist rumblings have swiftly extinguished them before they could even get off the ground.143 Susan Faludi, the author who developed the backlash theory, has questioned the reading of the current moment as one of backlash, suggesting instead that feminism itself lost its way, imploding under the weight of its own choices.144 We have been living in an era of performative feminism, marked by the “Girlboss” and “Notorious RBG,” where what passes for feminism is a $920 Christian Dior t-shirt emblazoned with “We Should All Be Feminists.”145 According to Faludi, “[f]eminism made a Faustian bargain with celebrity culture. Now it’s paying the price.”146

That this type of pop feminism might lead to feminist malaise is no surprise. In its effort to stand for everyone (or at least all women), it doesn’t stand for anything. When her original book on backlash was published in 1991, Faludi was asked how women might respond: “What unites women is the blatant, ugly evidence of oppression.”147 But the modern, bland version of feminism has nothing to say about oppression and hides all the ugly evidence. There is no rage to harness. Instead, this feminism, like the neoliberalism in which it arose, emphasizes individual choice above all. We can see this in Sheryl Sandberg’s much maligned book, Lean In, which focused on the choices available to already privileged women rather than structural or policy changes that would help their less fortunate sisters. An exit poll from the 2016 election found that only one-fifth of millennial women disagreed that feminism “is about personal choice, not politics.”148 As a keychain from the now defunct women’s co-working space The Wing puts it, this feminism stands for “girls doing whatever the fuck they want.”149

If this review is correct about the decline of women-centered orientation on the left, Suk’s book could serve as a clarion call for those who fail to see how misogyny continues to operate. Racialized state violence can be—and now often is—captured on our phones and police bodycams. Viral video evidence has played a key role in the Black Lives Matter movement.150 There is no comparable documentation of misogyny. The key sites of sex inequality—care, reproductive rights, domestic violence, and sexual abuse—are private.151 Misogyny thus remains safely ensconced behind the closed doors of the bedroom, the doctor’s office, the nursery. What you see is Karen’s public exercise of white privilege; what you don’t is Karen’s private experience of violence, exploitation, and lack of bodily autonomy.152 The point here is not to play Oppression Olympics but to recognize, with the help of Suk and others, that women can be both subjects and objects of oppression.

In formulating her theory of misogyny, Suk suggests that she is borrowing from the writings of philosopher Kate Manne. According to Suk, Manne treats “[m]isogyny [a]s the vigilante punishment of women who challenge male power and endeavor to reset the presumed entitlements of a patriarchal society.”153 Suk suggests that Manne is focused on “overentitled men trying to control women directly,” whereas she will attend to “the collective overentitlement of society designed and controlled by overempowered men to the benefits and enrichments that flow from women’s losses and sacrifices.”154

Yet it appears that Manne is the author who places more emphasis on misogyny as a general force, describing it as “a property of social environments in which women are liable to encounter hostility due to the enforcement and policing of social norms,”155 whereas Suk more often understands misogyny as something done by men to women.156 For example, she explains that the “collective overentitlement by society to women’s forebearance flows from men’s overempowerment,” and that this is functionally put into place with “laws that effectively concentrate decision-making power in men, locking in their power to control collective institutions.”157 Rather than a force field of gender relations that we are all stuck in and unconsciously enforce, Suk’s account places the blame on men: “overentitlement is not eradicated as long as empowered men who benefit from women’s forbearance continue to regard it as their natural set of baseline entitlements.”158

Suk assumes that the key divides on the laws and policies that enforce misogyny—with the lack of support for care and limits on reproductive rights as two prime examples—are between men and women and thus that women are basically united on these issues. But the legal scaffolding upholding the societal arrangements of misogyny she critiques are not a result of sex-based splits in the polity, nor are women (or men)159 by any means a politically united group.

Women have always been on both sides of the key issues affecting women’s lives. In a foundational study of the politics of abortion from which this review borrows its title, Professor Kristin Luker argued that the politics of abortion are the politics of motherhood.160 In other words, fights over abortion were one of the original “mommy wars,” with those favoring abortion rights in support of expanding women’s roles in public life and those favoring abortion restrictions in support of limiting women’s role to the home. Women straddled both sides of these debates.161 The extent to which sex ever drove policy preferences on issues like abortion and care is contested.162

If it was unsettled whether sex ever played a substantial role in American attitudes on matters of care and abortion, it is now clear that partisanship trumps all.163 Consider views on abortion. Recent polling shows that 61% of Americans believe that abortion should be legal in most or all cases.164 Views on this issue are far more sharply divided by party (with 80% of Democrats and 38% of Republicans expressing this view) than by gender (63% women and 58% men).165 So too with paid leave. Seventy percent of all voters are in favor of some form of paid leave.166 But again, views track party (82% of Democrats in support as compared with 58% of Republicans) far more than sex (72% women and 67% men).167 It’s not that there is no difference by gender; women in both parties tend to be more supportive of progressive policies on issues like care. But partisan difference dwarfs the gender divide.168

One of the most obvious ways to observe partisanship as the driving force behind misogynistic laws is in the divide between red and blue states on these issues. States with more progressive laws on abortion and care are states that lean left; states with less progressive laws on abortion and care are states that lean right.169 One upshot of this is that misogynistic laws vary quite considerably across the country, with some left-leaning states providing paid family leave and guaranteeing the right to abortion with no cutoff, and many right-leaning states providing no paid leave and banning abortion.170

So far, I have focused on partisan divides. But there are rifts among women on the left, too. Suk studiously avoids these. In her discussion of #MeToo, she focuses on Harvey Weinstein, an obvious villain,171 rather than edge cases, like Aziz Ansari,172 or any of the due process or other concerns raised by some feminists.173 Transgender rights too have divided feminists.174 It’s not that major cleavages within feminism are new.175 Yet Suk’s avoidance of the fissures among feminists and within feminism maintains an illusion of feminist unity. In reality, there is an unavoidable trade-off when it comes to the politics of womanhood: make it about all women and it stands for everyone but not much; make it about the issue and it stands for something but not everyone.176

If it’s not (just) men who are at the root of the misogynistic laws and policies that Suk identifies, then what is? I would proffer that it has something to do with intersecting ideologies of the proper role of government and the proper role of women.177 We can see these ideologies playing out in the polling and politics of the law and policies of care. While Americans show wide levels of support for paid leave,178 there is also wide disagreement about how to pay for it.179 Republicans are wary of a new government program and prefer employers to foot the bill.180

Opposition to government-funded care programs (either paid leave or childcare) reflects in part the fundamentally different role of the state in the United States as compared with the European countries that Suk highlights, such as France and Germany. The lack of state support for care that Suk identifies is part of a broader phenomenon in the United States, where we lack a range of social programs that require redistribution.181 Suk speaks of the need for legal and policy “translation” in migrating laws and policies from Europe to the United States.182 But it’s hard to translate these types of policies when our language of social welfare is so distinct from these social democracies; you wind up with gibberish. In a country of “pull yourself up by the bootstraps,” those who are unable to help themselves don’t get much help.183

It may be that there is, not blanket opposition to government spending (think the military) or even spending that entails redistribution (think Social Security), but an aversion that can be primed with the right message from the right messenger.184 We can see this time and again when it comes to the politics of care. A half century ago, universal childcare had strong bipartisan support when it was proposed in the Comprehensive Childhood Development Act.185 But Richard Nixon vetoed it for its “family-weakening implications” and concern about “communal approaches to child-rearing over against the family-centered approach.”186 Fifty years later, the same talking points are still in play. In 2021, Senate Minority Leader Mitch McConnell stoked fears of an intrusive (and incompetent) nanny state, calling the proposed childcare plan in Build Back Better a “toddler takeover.” “Buckle up, parents. What could go wrong?”187

So if we’re willing to spend big on some things, why not care? Democrats passed several large spending packages with a redistributive component188 but could not manage to include care, even after the country experimented with its first ever national paid leave program during the COVID-19 pandemic.189 In Suk’s discussion of Prohibition, she notes the political benefits of universal programs.190 But policies like paid leave and early childcare that benefit young families are used only by a subset of the population and thus are not political priorities for most Americans.191 Moreover, it’s not clear that well-off families with young children or expecting them would have sufficient incentives to support these policies.192

And then we return to misogyny. Our nation’s policies on childcare are, like abortion, about the politics of motherhood.193 Americans have long been ambivalent about mothers’ roles, including whether mothers should work in the market.194 Despite majority support for gender-neutral paid leave for newborns, there is more support for maternity leave than paternity leave.195 The majority of Americans believe that a household with two working parents is not the preferred family structure.196 Less than 20% of Americans think it is ideal if both parents work full time, and nearly half—including one-third of Democrats—think it best if one parent is a full-time caregiver.197 Of that latter group, half think the stay-at-home parent could be a mom or a dad.198 But given ongoing inequality in the distribution of reproductive labor, a wish for a stay-at-home parent is most often fulfilled by a stay-at-home mom.199

Turning to reproductive rights, they might not seem to fit neatly with this story. The lack of support for reproductive rights easily tracks ambivalence about the role of mothers.200 The intersection with an aversion to big government is harder to see. In the United States at least, reproductive rights have been framed as a freedom from government intrusion into a woman’s right to control her body.201 In a country where for some segment of the population big government is the death knell of a policy position, framing abortion this way might have been politically savvy.

But as Suk’s description of the German approach to abortion makes clear, this libertarian approach is not inevitable. In Germany, the constitutional status of abortion implicates several elements of German Basic Law: equality between men and women, women’s entitlement to care of the community, and the state’s duty to protect life.202 To fulfill its duty to unborn life, the state has an obligation to “confront the dangers attached to the existing and foreseeable living conditions of the woman and the family which could destroy the woman’s willingness to carry the child to term,” which would include “attend[ing] to the problems and difficulties, which the mother could encounter during pregnancy,” and “viewing motherhood and childcare as work.”203

A more robust conception of reproductive rights—and a more robust conception of freedom in general—often requires support, especially for the most vulnerable.204 The right to an abortion “on demand” might be thought of not as the apex of reproductive freedom but merely its beginning. A substantial reason for abortion is lack of resources.205 Real reproductive choice means not only having the right to terminate a pregnancy free from government interference, which is of course essential, but also the right to continue the pregnancy with the resources needed to do so. As Suk explains, “the full range of reproductive activities” runs from “begetting and bearing a child to birthing and raising one.”206 Post-Roe America marries twin goals of the right: moms at home without the government footing the bill. The states that haved moved to restrict abortion the most are the very same ones that support women and children the least, with predictable consequences for low-income women and their families.207

As this part has suggested, many factors go into explaining the misogynistic laws and policies in the United States that fail to support reproductive rights and care. Gender is a big part of this story. But it’s not that men support misogynistic laws and women oppose them. Views about the proper role of mothers undergirding the politics of both abortion and care track partisan identification far more closely than sex.

This all might be changing. There has long been a gender gap in partisan identification, with women tending to vote more Democrat and men tending to vote more Republican.208 This gender gap is widening among young people, with the number of both young female liberals and young male conservatives growing.209 If these trends continue, we might see a world that looks more like the one that Suk envisions. But we’re not there yet.

Suk has a number of ideas for changing misogynistic laws. One of her central proposals is to empower women, placing them in more leadership roles in all branches of government and in important roles in the private sector. However, just as men are not at the root of the political problem behind misogynistic laws, women are unlikely to be the solution. Because women are not a cohesive political class that uniformly supports the types of changes Suk envisions, empowering women is more symbolic than material. And because women are not united in their material interests, empowering some relatively privileged women is unlikely to meaningfully change misogynistic laws in a way that helps all women. Finally, because women do not represent a coherent political group, there has to be some other political constituency that would create the change she wants, and this review suggests where we might find it.

Suk argues that women are a solution to the laws of misogyny. Get more women in power, and this will get more women empowered. I am skeptical of both the means and the ends of her proposals. First, the means. Suk suggests that we embrace gender-conscious policies to promote women’s representation, like the gender quotas in political positions and corporate boards that are found across the globe.210 I fear that the idea of gender-based quotas common in other countries does not translate so well here. In a racially pluralistic society like the United States with a history of de jure and de facto racial oppression, it is hard to imagine getting political support for gender quotas without also implementing racial quotas. This is what we’ve seen in California, which passed gender and race diversity requirements for the boards of public companies based there.211 Because sex classifications are subject to a lower level of scrutiny, the gender requirement has so far withstood a federal constitutional challenge, but the race requirement has not.212 Given the politics of race and gender at this moment,213 it is hard to imagine a constituency that would support a gender quota without a race quota.

Still further, a law that makes it easier to pursue sex-based affirmative action, as Suk suggests,214 without doing the same for race-based affirmative action, could lead to unintended, and undesirable, consequences.215 While Suk does not address education, it is worth dwelling on that context for a moment. Because of the current gender gap in higher education, boys are now frequently benefitting from affirmative action by colleges seeking to maintain a gender balance.216 It is perhaps no coincidence that most of the plaintiffs in the Court’s biggest university admissions cases in the last two decades were white women.217 With direct reliance on race in admissions now verboten,218 and with Black boys lagging white boys in school,219 we will be left with affirmative action for (mostly white) boys and men.

It is also unlikely that gender quotas would bring about the results Suk desires. As Professor Kyla Schuller argues, proposals to ease feminist woes by putting more women in power are based in “delusions that Girl Power will solve inequality, that if the investment bank Lehman Brothers were instead Lehman Sisters we would have a better kind of capitalism and that putting a woman in the White House will create a more moral empire.”220 There may be other reasons to increase women’s representation in the areas of public life where they are so seriously underrepresented, such as democratic legitimacy, role modeling, or productivity, but the connection to combatting misogyny is tenuous at best.

Suk relies on examples of gender quotas in politics from Europe, for example, France, where a 2008 constitutional amendment to promote women’s representation in elective offices and positions of responsibility was followed by laws requiring gender quotas on corporate boards, political parties, and other decision-making bodies, a 2014 comprehensive gender equality statute, and 2018 law requiring an equal pay index.221 Suk writes, “With women now constituting more than one-third of the legislature, the French Parliament adopted new legislation in 2018 creating an ‘equal pay index.’”222 But it’s not clear that it was getting more women in power that brought about these legal changes. Whatever social and political forces existed to support increasing women’s representation might also be behind support for other measures to help women.

In the United States, studies show that women do not govern differently than men.223 So too generally for judges and judging.224 For just a few illustrative examples, consider that the most female Supreme Court was the one that issued Dobbs and Kyrsten Sinema was one of two Democratic holdouts in the Senate on Build Back Better’s care provisions and on eliminating the filibuster to pass more Democratic legislation,225not to mention all the Republican women in Congress who shared these positions.226 Women are not the key to undoing misogyny.

Consider corporate boards. To the extent that the use of quotas is a remedy for discrimination against women in board selection, a reason that Suk cites,227 a quota can be justified as an anti-misogyny measure. Yet Suk also argues that a gender quota is a remedy for “excessive concentration of power in men,” citing research showing how companies perform better when their boards include women.228 However, other research calls into question the connection between women board members and corporate performance,229 and to the extent any correlation has been found, there is no evidence of a causal effect.230 But even conceding a causal connection, enhancing corporate performance is about productivity, not combatting misogyny.

Returning to Lehman Sisters, research shows that women investors tend to outperform men; this has been explained as resulting from women’s average lower risk tolerance.231 Suk writes about the 2008 financial collapse in Iceland, which she says “was largely understood to be caused by overempowered men who had enriched themselves by taking excessive risks, and whose costs were eventually borne by the rest of the nation.”232 But is this an example of misogyny or of class conflict and lax financial regulation?233 Promoting more women into leadership as a response might be more about combatting bad governance than combatting misogyny.234

There is a mismatch, then, between Suk’s diagnosis and this part of Suk’s prescriptions. Whereas the diagnosis is material, the prescription is symbolic. Whereas the diagnosis is structural, the prescription is individual. Here, Suk’s critique, which could be a critique of a social order that fails to provide state support in a way that largely falls on the backs of women, winds up catering to a neoliberal feminist vision focused on elites.235 This is especially so if what Suk identifies as the core legal regime of misogyny has a lot to do with class, with wealthy women able to afford both childcare and access to reproductive care, while poor and middle-class women bear the brunt of these misogynistic laws.236 On this view, a solution premised on elite women and elite institutions is a particularly ill fit.237 Focusing on sex alone lets capitalism off too easy.

Suk concludes her book by arguing for procedural overhauls in our democracy, such as moving to unicameralism, correcting Senate malapportionment, and eliminating the filibuster.238 This is premised on the view that the problem of misogynistic laws is a problem of misalignment.239 The people want to get rid of misogyny, but our undemocratic institutions don’t effectively translate these popular preferences into matching policies. This may be true on some laws of misogyny, such as those governing abortion.240 But this is not true of all of these issues. I fear that at least on some policies, misogyny, or at least ambivalence about laws that support women and the things associated with them, like care, may run deeper.241 Changing misogynistic laws might require not only changing government structures but changing hearts and minds.

Changing hearts and minds might sound like a tall order, but it’s probably more feasible than changing the Constitution, and parties could provide a path forward. In an era of partisan divides, parties play the central role in translating the meaning of policies for citizens.242 In other words, if your party supports a policy, you likely will too. Is there any hope of getting Republicans to shift on some of these misogynistic laws and policies? The possibilities seem dim, and out of the question on abortion, but let me suggest one area where we have already seen some bipartisan support and we might be able to get more. The left and the right have occasionally come together on care.243

While some of the right’s views of women (best at home) and views of the state (best kept small) are in obvious tension with robust state support for care, aspects of the right’s ideology are compatible with such policies. Foremost is the idea of limiting abortion. State support for parenting reduces one of the main reasons for abortion: a lack of resources to support a child.244 In Germany, for example, the state’s duty to protect unborn life has been interpreted to include an obligation by the state to ensure that pregnancies are not terminated due to material hardship.245 As Suk writes of the German approach, “there are many ways that a state can be pro-life, including by investing in a “‘child-friendly society.’”246

We can see hints of a shift in embracing this type of thinking on the right. Parts of the pro-family wing of the Republican party have gotten behind the state’s role in supporting care to promote family health and reduce abortion,247 just as parts of the business wing of the Republican party have gotten behind the state’s role in supporting care to make work and family more compatible.248 A more economically populist Republican party may be more open to these types of policies.249 Post-Dobbs, Republicans are facing pressure to move in this direction.250 As one Republican advisor has argued, “[a]s a result of that ruling, millions more babies are going to be born, especially in red states, and, morally and economically, the GOP must demonstrate its commitment to caring for those babies and their parents.”251

Consider the Pregnant Workers Fairness Act, passed in late 2022 with remarkable bipartisan support, ten years after it was introduced in Congress but just months after Dobbs came down.252 The law, which requires employers to provide reasonable accommodations to pregnant workers, was supported by some unlikely allies: the U.S. Chamber of Commerce, the ACLU, and the U.S. Conference of Catholic Bishops, as well as significant numbers of Republicans in both houses of Congress.253 Senator Bill Cassidy (R-La.), no feminist stalwart, described it as “a bipartisan bill”254 that is “pro-family, pro-mother, pro-baby, pro-employer, and pro-economy.”255 Another example of post-Dobbs bipartisanship on care is the Providing Urgent Maternal Protections for Nursing Mothers Act (PUMP Act).256 The law, passed in December 2022, expands rights around expressing breast milk at work. It passed the House with 276 votes and the Senate nearly unanimously.257 To be sure, neither the Pregnant Workers’ Fairness Act nor the PUMP Act required new government programs; they simply placed rather modest obligations on employers. Still, bipartisan support for these laws might be read as evidence of the potential for the left and the right to come together on care.

While the possibilities for more coming together on care seem (somewhat) plausible, on abortion, this seems like a pipe dream. Let us consider one possible framing—suggested by Suk’s telling of the German approach to abortion—that might move us forward. Recall that the German doctrine of abortion is guided by balancing three interests: the state’s obligation to unborn life, the state’s obligation to the care of mothers, and the state’s obligation to sex equality. Because of the burdens of pregnancy and parenting, the state may limit abortion only if it sufficiently supports pregnancy and parenting.258 “If the state proclaims an interest in transforming unborn lives into born children, the state has duties to the person who makes that process possible and carries it out. … In some situations, permitting abortion may be the only way for the state to fulfill its duty.”259

In Suk’s translation of the German approach to abortion to the United States, she argues for applying the Thirteenth Amendment and especially the Takings Clause to abortion regulations.260 Suk hopes that such approaches would change people’s understanding of reproductive rights so that they would better appreciate how limits on such rights are extractive of women’s labor. Yet a takings approach would allow the state to restrict abortion so long as it compensates for it, thus missing one of the key ingredients of reproductive choice. And the takings theory as Suk tells it is premised on compensation for renting the womb during the pregnancy. This property-based framework not only misses the crucial need for support after the child is born but, as Professor Deborah Dinner has noted, risks reinforcing a notion of pregnancy as an individual private affair—precisely what Suk argues against.261

I would turn to a different and quite unexpected place to see at least inklings of a German-type approach to abortion right here in America. One of the most commented-upon aspects of the Dobbs oral argument was Justice Amy Coney Barrett’s question about “safe haven” laws that permit parents to leave newborns at hospitals or fire stations to be placed for adoption.262 Commentators on the left rightly pilloried Justice Barrett for suggesting that a pregnancy is costless so long as there is a way to part with the resulting child.263 But there might have been something important lurking in Justice Barrett’s question: she ties abortion rights to the legal infrastructure surrounding pregnancy and parenting. While her view of adequate state supports is woefully incomplete, conditioning the state’s ability to regulate abortion on the state’s provision of related support echoes the German approach.

Could this be a place where the right and the left can see eye to eye on abortion? Even this suggestion is mighty optimistic, to say the least. Maybe there is little to no political constituency for an approach where everyone loses. For the left, there is no absolute right to abortion, but rather mothers’ interests gain more weight when the state fails to provide adequate supports. For the right, there is no absolute government power to restrict abortion, but rather the state can place more restrictions on abortion the more support it provides.264 Such an approach may also require a substantial overhaul in how we think about rights, shifting away from rights as trumps and toward interests that must be weighed and balanced.265 We are probably a long way away from a politics of abortion that aims to reduce it rather than to ban abortion or to permit it in more absolute terms.266 Still, perhaps both sides can agree that no one wins when a pregnancy is terminated solely for a lack of resources that the state could provide.

Even if we achieve the seemingly impossible and get federal laws like paid family leave passed, a final question is whether even that is enough to combat the type of deeply rooted gender attitudes at the heart of the inequality Suk highlights. Law can do a lot, but it may still fall short. In Sweden—often depicted as the land of feminist fairy tale—laws like those that reserve two months of baby leave for dads267 and insist on gender-neutral preschools268 have made huge inroads on traditional gender roles, for example, dramatically increasing the amount of time dads take off from work after a baby is born.269 Yet even there, moms continue to take the vast majority of leave (almost four times as much as dads), and the main reason, after finances, is the mother’s preference.270 It may be that law is necessary but not sufficient to get us beyond misogyny.

After Misogyny provides an opportunity for much-needed reflection on the state of feminism and women in a time of uncertainty over feminist progress, backlash, and chaos. By sidestepping these preoccupations of the day, Suk returns us to one of the perennial questions of feminism: whether women make up a coherent class, in perception and in reality. These core questions of feminism need to be asked and answered again and again, as our world—and our understandings of it—continue to change. Taking stock of the idea of women as a political class, as this review has endeavored to do, is a substantial undertaking, and one that this review just begins. It may raise more questions—about sex, gender, race, class, identity, and politics—than it answers. Suk’s important book invites readers to take up these questions and more, all while reminding us of the all too unfortunate reality that the law of misogyny is still with us.

1 

SeeJulie C. Suk, After Misogyny: How the Law Fails Women and What to Do About It (2023).

2 

See Constance Grady, The Waves of Feminism, and Why People Keep Fighting over Them, Explained, Vox (July 20, 2018, 9:57 AM), https://www.vox.com/2018/3/20/16955588/feminism-waves-explained-first-second-third-fourth.

3 

See Lisa Lerer & Sydney Ember, Kamala Harris Makes History as First Woman and Woman of Color as Vice President, N.Y. Times (Aug. 26, 2021), https://www.nytimes.com/2020/11/07/us/politics/kamala-harris.html.

4 

See Julie Hirschfeld Davis, Nancy Pelosi Elected Speaker as Democrats Take Control of House, N.Y. Times (Jan. 3, 2019), https://www.nytimes.com/2019/01/03/us/politics/nancy-pelosi-speaker-116th-congress.html.

5 

See Emma Green, “We Are Preparing to Shatter the Highest Glass Ceiling in Our Country,”The Atlantic (July 26, 2016), https://www.theatlantic.com/politics/archive/2016/07/hillary-clinton-first-female-presidential-nominee/493163/.

6 

See Robert Barnes, Four Women on the Supreme Court Would Bring Historic, Near Gender Parity for Institution Long Dominated by White Men, Wash. Post (Feb. 27, 2022, 6:48 PM), https://www.washingtonpost.com/politics/2022/02/27/ketanji-jackson-supreme-court/.

7 

See Anna North, 7 Positive Changes That Have Come From the #MeToo Movement, Vox (Oct. 4, 2019, 7:00 AM), https://www.vox.com/identities/2019/10/4/20852639/me-too-movement-sexual-harassment-law-2019.

8 

See generallyRichard Reeves, Of Boys and Men: Why the Modern Male Is Struggling, Why It Matters, and What to Do About It (2022).

9 

See generallySusan Faludi, Backlash: The Undeclared War Against American Women (1991).

10 

See id. at xx (noting that even a false perception of equality can trigger backlash, a “pre-emptive strike” well before women reach the “finish line”).

11 

See, e.g., The #MeToo Backlash, Harv. Bus. Rev. (Sept.–Oct. 2019), https://hbr.org/2019/09/the-metoo-backlash; Constance Grady, The Mounting, Undeniable Me Too Backlash, Vox (Feb. 3, 2023, 6:30 AM), https://www.vox.com/culture/23581859/me-too-backlash-susan-faludi-weinstein-roe-dobbs-depp-heard.

12 

Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Org., 142 S. Ct. 2228 (2022); see also Linda Greenhouse, Is There Any Twinge of Regret Among the Anti-Abortion Justices?, N.Y. Times (June 23, 2023), https://www.nytimes.com/2023/06/23/opinion/abortion-supreme-court-dobbs.html (“Valuing fetal life over the lives of women and girls was no doubt a feature, not a bug, in the majority’s view; that was, after all, the point of Dobbs.”).

13 

See Matthew Cullen, Trump Was Found Liable for Sexual Abuse and Defamation, N.Y. Times (May 9, 2023), https://www.nytimes.com/2023/05/09/briefing/trump-carroll-civil-trial-biden-debt.html.

14 

See Nellie Bowles, Jordan Peterson, Custodian of the Patriarchy, N.Y. Times (May 18, 2018), https://www.nytimes.com/2018/05/18/style/jordan-peterson-12-rules-for-life.html; Shanti Das, Inside the Violent, Misogynistic World of TikTok’s New Star, Andrew Tate, The Guardian (Aug. 6, 2022 12:48 AM), https://www.theguardian.com/technology/2022/aug/06/andrew-tate-violent-misogynistic-world-of-tiktok-new-star; Equimundo, State of American Men 2023, (2023), https://www.equimundo.org/wp-content/uploads/2023/05/STATE-OF-AMERICAN-MEN-2023.pdf (describing “observable backsliding and backlash” in the wake of the #MeToo movement, noting that “some men—particularly younger men—are moving backward in their support of gender equality”).

15 

Michelle Goldberg, The Future Isn’t Female Anymore, N.Y. Times (June 17, 2022), https://www.nytimes.com/2022/06/17/opinion/roe-dobbs-abortion-feminism.html.

16 

Katy Steinmetz, The Transgender Tipping Point, Time (May 29, 2014), https://time.com/135480/transgender-tipping-point/.

17 

See, e.g., Michelle Goldberg, What Is a Woman?, New Yorker (July 28, 2014), https://www.newyorker.com/magazine/2014/08/04/woman-2; Elinor Burkett, What Makes a Woman?, N.Y. Times (June 6, 2015), https://www.nytimes.com/2015/06/07/opinion/sunday/what-makes-a-woman.html.

18 

See Adeel Hassan, States Passed a Record Number of Transgender Laws. Here’s What They Say, N.Y. Times (June 27, 2023), https://www.nytimes.com/2023/06/27/us/transgender-laws-states.html.

19 

See Jonathan Weisman, A Demand to Define ‘Woman’ Injects Gender Politics into Jackson’s Confirmation Hearings, N.Y. Times (Mar. 23, 2022), https://www.nytimes.com/2022/03/23/us/politics/ketanji-brown-jackson-woman-definition.html.

20 

See Graph Massara, The Complexities and Nuances of Transgender Coverage, Colum. Journalism Rev. (May 25, 2023), https://www.cjr.org/analysis/trans-coverage-guide-suggestions.php.

21 

See Julie Suk, Fordham Law, https://www.fordham.edu/school-of-law/faculty/directory/full-time/julie-suk/ (last visited May 24, 2023).

22 

Suk, supra note 1, at 3.

23 

Id. at 4–7.

24 

Id. at 9.

25 

Reva Siegel, Why Equal Protection No Longer Protects: The Evolving Forms of Status-Enforcing State Action, 49 Stan. L. Rev. 1111, 1119 (1997).

26 

Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190 (1976).

27 

Suk, supra note 1, at 41.

28 

See Cary Franklin, The Anti-Stereotyping Principle in Constitutional Sex Discrimination Law, 85 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 83 (2010).

29 

See, e.g., Suk, supra note 1, at 46–47 (highlighting possible harms of gender-neutral statutory rape law to girls); id. at 58–59 (suggesting that gender stereotypes that led to women’s exclusion from military conscription might be better addressed by valuing childbearing and childrearing than by making women register for the draft).

30 

Id. at 63.

31 

Id. at 73.

32 

Id.

33 

Id. at 123.

34 

Suk, supra note 1, at 88.

35 

Id.

36 

See id. at 3; id. at 9 (citing arrangements that “concentrate decision-making power in men” so that they “control collective institutions”).

37 

See, e.g., Joan Didion, The Women’s Movement, N.Y. Times (July 30, 1972), https://www.nytimes.com/1972/07/30/archives/the-womens-movement-women.html (explaining, in a critique of the women’s movement, its “Marxist” ideology: “[t]o make an omelette you need not only those broken eggs but someone ‘oppressed’ to break them: every revolutionist is presumed to understand that, and also every woman, which either does or does not make 51 per cent of the population of the United States a potentially revolutionary class,” and that “the creation of this revolutionary class was from the virtual beginning the ‘idea’ of the women’s movement”).

38 

See id.

39 

Suk, supra note 1, at 3.

40 

Catharine A. MacKinnon, Toward a Feminist Theory of the State 215 (1989) (“Inequality because of sex defines and situates women as women. If the sexes were equal, women would not be sexually subjected. Sexual force would be exceptional, consent to sex could be commonly real, and sexually violated women would be believed. If the sexes were equal, women would not be economically subjected, their desperation and marginality cultivated, their enforced dependency exploited sexually or economically. Women would have speech, privacy, authority, respect, and more resources than they have now. Rape and pornography would be recognized as violations, and abortion would be both rare and actually guaranteed. In the United States, it is acknowledged that the state is capitalist; it is not acknowledged that it is male.”); Redstockings Manifesto, Redstockings (1969), https://www.redstockings.org/index.php/rs-manifesto (stating that “[w]omen are an oppressed class” and that “the agents of our oppression [are] men”).

41 

Suk, supra note 1, at 3–4.

42 

See id. at 19–20.

43 

What the left has tended to see as sex disadvantage, the right has tended to celebrate as sex difference. See generallyMarjorie J. Spruill, Divided We Stand: The Battle over Women’s Rights and Family Values That Polarized American Politics 1 (2017) (discussing battles between the progressive women’s rights movement and the conservative “pro-family” women’s movement).

44 

See infra notes 45–89 and accompanying text.

45 

Goldberg, supra note 15.

46 

What To Do About Feminism, The Drift (Jan. 31, 2022), https://www.thedriftmag.com/what-to-do-about-feminism/ (identifying a “profound malaise” about feminism, which is described as a “movement in crisis”).

47 

Goldberg, supra note 15.

48 

Cassie Miller, SPLC Poll Finds Substantial Support for “Great Replacement” Theory and Other Hard-Right Ideas, S. Poverty L. Ctr. (June 1, 2022), https://www.splcenter.org/news/2022/06/01/poll-finds-support-great-replacement-hard-right-ideas.

49 

See id. While the poll asked for views on feminism rather for the salience of women as a subordinated political category, we can take the question as a proxy for views on sex-based identity politics.

50 

Id. (among Republicans, citing agreement levels of 52% of young women, 62% of young men, 51% of older women, and 42% of older men).

51 

Only small numbers of older Democrats (10% of women and 4% of men) agreed. Id.

52 

Id.

53 

Id.

54 

Miller, supra note 48.

55 

Id. An earlier 2020 Pew study found 64% agreeing that feminism was “empowering” (68% women and 60% men; 77% Democrat women and 56% Republican women) and 30% agreeing that it was “outdated” (25% women and 34% men; 18% Democrat women and 36% Republican women). See Amanda Barroso, 61% of U.S. Women Say “Feminist” Describes Them Well; Many See Feminism as Empowering, Polarizing, Pew Rsch. Ctr. (July 7, 2020), https://www.pewresearch.org/short-reads/2020/07/07/61-of-u-s-women-say-feminist-describes-them-well-many-see-feminism-as-empowering-polarizing/.

56 

Miller, supra note 48.

57 

Id. Older men and women are aligned in their views here, whereas younger men and women diverge. See infra notes 201–202 and accompanying text on a growing political gender divide among younger Americans.

58 

Id.

59 

See, e.g., Ruby Hamad, White Tears/Brown Scars: How White Feminism Betrays Women of Color (2020); Kyla Schuller, The Trouble with White Women (2021); Koa Beck, White Feminism: from the Suffragettes to Influencers and Who They Leave Behind (2021); Rafia Zakaria, Against White Feminism (2021); Ilsa Govan & Tilman Smith, What’s Up With White Women?: Unpacking Sexism and White Privilege in Pursuit of Racial Justice (2021); Regina Jackson & Saira Rao, White Women: Everything You Already Know About Your Own Racism and How to Do Better (2022). A quick look on Google Ngram reveals that the use of the term “white feminism” has exploded since 2011, even though its data stops at 2019. “White feminism,” Google Books Ngram Viewer, https://books.google.com/ngrams (search for “white feminism” from 2011 to 2019).

60 

Glenn Loury & Meghan Daum, The New Culture Wars [The Glenn Show] at 12:10–12:26, YouTube, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=6qLjQyQVWc0.

61 

Id.

62 

Aamina I. Khan & Sara Delgado, Why Emily Ratajkowski Defended Taylor Swift over That “F*cked Up” Ellen Degeneres Interview, Teen Vogue (Mar. 30, 2023), https://www.teenvogue.com/story/old-taylor-swift-interview-ellen-emily-ratajkowski.

63 

Ligaya Mishan, The March of the Karens, N.Y. Times (Aug. 12, 2021), https://www.nytimes.com/2021/08/12/t-magazine/white-women-karen.html.

64 

Charles M. Blow, How White Women Use Themselves as Instruments of Terror, N.Y. Times (May 27, 2020), https://www.nytimes.com/2020/05/27/opinion/racism-white-women.html; Cady Lang, How the “Karen Meme” Confronts the Violent History of White Womanhood, Time (last updated July 6, 2020 4:11 PM), https://time.com/5857023/karen-meme-history-meaning; Helen Lewis, The Mythology of Karen, The Atlantic (Aug. 19, 2020), https://www.theatlantic.com/international/archive/2020/08/karen-meme-coronavirus/615355/; Robin Abcarian, Is the ‘Karen’ Meme Sexist? Maybe, but It’s Also Apt, L.A. Times (May 23, 2020 3:10 AM), https://www.latimes.com/opinion/story/2020-05-23/column-karen-meme-white-women-behaving-badly.

65 

See Mishan, supra note 63; Lewis, supra note 64; Damon Young, Yeah, It’s Time to Bury the Cutesy “Karen” Nickname for Dangerous White Women, Root (July 2, 2020), https://www.theroot.com/yeah-its-time-to-bury-the-cutesy-karen-nickname-for-da-1844248172 (calling for a moratorium on the nickname because it “feels weird and wrong that the Karen has become the contemporary face of white supremacy when white men are way more destructive”).

66 

Karen Attiah, The “Karen” Memes and Jokes Aren’t Sexist or Racist. Let a Karen Explain, Wash. Post (Apr. 28, 2020), https://www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/2020/04/28/karen-memes-jokes-arent-sexist-or-racist-let-karen-explain.

67 

Catharine A. MacKinnon, From Practice to Theory, or What Is a White Woman Anyway?, 4 Yale J.L. & Feminism 13, 18–19 (1991) (focusing on the presumed racism of the white woman: “she cries rape when Emmett Till looks at her sideways, she manipulates white men’s very real power with the lifting of her very well-manicured little finger,” “[s]he makes an appearance … as the Central Park Jogger, the classy white madonna who got herself raped and beaten nearly to death”).

68 

Open Letters to Catharine MacKinnon, 4 Yale J.L. & Feminism 177, 177 (1991).

69 

Id. at 183 (“[A]ll women need to reclaim and insist upon the dignity of the feminist project, which includes very real oppression suffered by women, despite any access women may have to social privilege (and we include ourselves as recipients of social privilege. …”).

70 

See David Schleicher, Episode 47: Julie Suk, Digging a Hole: The Legal Theory Podcast (Apr. 11, 2023), https://www.diggingaholepodcast.com/episodes/suk.

71 

See, e.g., Yale Law Women, Yale Law School Faculty and Students Speak Up About Gender: Ten Years Later 13–14 (2012), https://ylw.yale.edu/wp-content/uploads/2013/03/YLW-Speak-Up-Study.pdf; Adam Neufeld, Costs of an Outdated Pedagogy? Study on Gender at Harvard Law School, 13 Am. Univ. J. Gender, Soc. Poly & L. 511, 561–62 (2005) (“The study results show systemic differences between female and male students’ experiences at Harvard Law School in areas ranging from classroom participation and self-confidence to grades and employment.”); Yale Law Women, Yale Law School Faculty and Students Speak About Gender (2002) (reporting the results of a study investigating male and female experiences at Yale Law School); Lani Guinier et al., Becoming Gentlemen: Women’s Experiences at One Ivy League Law School, 143 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1, 4 (1994); Janet Taber et al., Gender, Legal Education, and the Legal Profession: An Empirical Study of Stanford Law Students and Graduates, 40 Stan. L. Rev. 1209, 1219–22 (1988) (examining differing experiences of men and women at Stanford Law School).

72 

Schleicher, supra note 70.

73 

The most recent study out of the University of Virginia Law School was begun by faculty members several years before its publication. See Molly Bishop Shadel et al., Gender Differences in Law School Classroom Participation: The Key Role of Social Context, 108 Va. L. Rev. Online 30 (2022).

74 

See sources cited supra note 71.

75 

She fell from number 32 to number 40 in most-cited law professors between 2000 and 2021. Compare Fred R. Shapiro, The Most-Cited Legal Scholars, 29 J. Legal Studies 409, 424 (2000), with Fred R. Shapiro, The Most-Cited Legal Scholars Revisited, 88 Chi. L. Rev. 1595, 1603 (2021).

76 

See Andrew Cohen, Moving Forward: Faculty Approves Race and Law Course Requirement in Order to Graduate, Berkeley L. (Feb. 18, 2022), https://www.law.berkeley.edu/article/faculty-approves-race-and-law-course-requirement/.

77 

Mary Joe Frug, A Postmodern Feminist Legal Manifesto (an Unfinished Draft), 105 Harv. L. Rev. 1045 (1992); Barbara Johnson, The Postmodern in Feminism, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 1076 (1992) (response to Frug); Ruth Colker, The Example of Lesbians: A Posthumous Reply to Professor Mary Joe Frug, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 1084 (1992) (response to Frug); Martha Minow, Incomplete Correspondence: An Unsent Letter to Mary Joe Frug, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 1096 (1992) (response to Frug); Cynthia Grant Bowman, Street Harassment and the Informal Ghettoization of Women, 106 Harv. L. Rev. 517 (1993).

78 

Gillian K. Hadfield, Flirting with Science: Richard Posner on the Bioeconomics of Sexual Man, 106 Harv. L. Rev. 479 (1992) (reviewing Richard A. Posner, Sex and Reason (1992)); Book Note, An Unlady-Like Response to Legal Conceptions of Women, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 2104 (1992) (reviewing Faludi, supra note 9).

79 

Note, Inner-City Single-Sex Schools: Educational Reform or Invidious Discrimination, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 1741 (1992); Note, Beyond “Batson”: Eliminating Gender-Based Peremptory Challenges, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 1920 (1992); Note, What’s Culture Got to Do with It? Excising the Harmful Tradition of Female Circumcision, 103 Harv. L. Rev. 1944 (1993).

80 

Recent Case, D.C. Circuit Invalidates FCC’s Gender-Based Policies, 106 Harv. L. Rev. 804 (1993); Recent Case, Third Circuit Rules That Denial of Promotion Based on an Equally Applied Legitimate Subjective Criterion Is Not Discrimination, 103 Harv. L. Rev. 2039 (1993) (discussing a sex discrimination case classified under “gender discrimination” by the Review).

81 

Recent Case, New York Court of Appeals Refuses to Adopt a Functional Analysis in Defining Family Relationships, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 941 (1992); Note, Into the Mouths of Babes: La Familia Latina and Federally Funded Child Welfare, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 1319 (1992); Book Note, Divorced from Reality, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 2110 (1992) (reviewing Martha A. Fineman, The Illusion of Equality: The Rhetoric and Reality of Divorce Reform (1991)); Recent Case, Sixth Circuit Holds That Expert Testimony Is Not Needed to Establish a Standard of Care in Surrogacy Cases, 106 Harv. L. Rev. 951 (1993).

82 

Recent Case, California Supreme Court Holds Police Department Vicariously Liable for Rape Committed by On-Duty Police Officer, 105 Harv. L. Rev. 947 (1992); Recent Case, New Jersey Supreme Court Holds that Lack of Consent Constitutes “Physical Force”, 106 Harv. L. Rev. 969 (1993).

83 

Note, Pornography, Equality, and a Discrimination-Free Workplace: A Comparative Perspective, 106 Harv. L. Rev. 1075 (1993).

84 

Developments in the Law, Legal Responses to Domestic Violence, 103 Harv. L. Rev. 1498 (1993).

85 

Recent Case, Kentucky Supreme Court Finds that Criminalization of Homosexual Sodomy Violates State Constitutional Guarantees of Privacy and Equal Protection, 103 Harv. L. Rev. 1370 (1993); Note, Constitutional Limits on Anti-Gay-Rights Initiatives, 103 Harv. L. Rev. 1905 (1993).

86 

Khiara M. Bridges, Race in the Roberts Court, 136 Harv. L. Rev. 23 (2022); Michele Goodwin, Complicit Bias and the Supreme Court, 136 Harv. L. Rev. F. 119 (2022) (response to Bridges); Dorothy E. Roberts, Racism, Abolition, and Historical Resemblance, 136 Harv. L. Rev. F. 37 (2022) (response to Bridges); Nina Varsava, Precedent, Reliance, and Dobbs, 136 Harv. L. Rev. 1845 (2023).

87 

Claire Huntington, Pragmatic Family Law, 136 Harv. L. Rev. 1501 (2023); Recent Case, Seventh Circuit Entrenches Conduct Categories for FMLA Interference Claims, 136 Harv. L. Rev. 1477 (2023); Recent Case, Japanese Supreme Court Holds That Forcing Couples to Share a Surname Is Constitutional, 135 Harv. L. Rev. 1504 (2022).

88 

Jennifer Levi & Kevin Barry, “Made to Feel Broken”: Ending Conversion Practices and Saving Transgender Lives, 136 Harv. L. Rev. 1112 (2023) (reviewing Florence Ashley, Banning Transgender Conversion Practices: A Legal and Policy Analysis (2022)); Note, Romer Has It, 136 Harv. L. Rev. 1936 (2023).

89 

Perhaps we’ve incorporated the feminist lens into various substantive legal areas rather than women being the primary focus, but even this is a noteworthy shift.

90 

See, e.g., The Editorial Board, The Ruling Overturning Roe Is an Insult to Women and the Judicial System, N.Y. Times (June 24, 2022), https://www.nytimes.com/2022/06/24/opinion/dobbs-ruling-roe-v-wade.html.

91 

See Shreenita Ghosh, et al., Covering #MeToo Across the News Spectrum: Political Accusation and Public Events as Drivers of Press Attention, 27 Intl J. Press/Pols. 158 (2020).

92 

Reeves, supra note 8, at 105–16 (tracing the ways that the left recognizes gender inequality that harms women and girls but not gender inequality that harms men and boys).

93 

Or perhaps movements that replace identity with class. See Steven Greenhouse, “The Success Is Inspirational”: The Fight for $15 Movement 10 Years On, The Guardian (Nov. 23, 2022), https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2022/nov/23/fight-for-15-movement-10-years-old; Katie Barrows & Ethan Miller, The New Labor Movement Is Young, Worker-Led and Winning, In These Times (May 9, 2022), https://inthesetimes.com/article/new-labor-movement-amazon-starbucks-union.

94 

See Arthur Schelsinger, Jr., The Crisis of American Masculinity, Esquire (1958) (writing that “[f]or a long time, [the American male] seemed utterly confident in his manhood, sure of his masculine role in society,” but by the mid-20th century, men came to view their masculinity “not as a fact but as a problem”).

95 

See, e.g., Christina Hoff Sommers, The War Against Boys: How Misguided Policies Are Harming Our Young Men (2000); Kay Hymowitz, Manning Up: How the Rise of Women Has Turned Men into Boys (2011); Josh Hawley, Manhood: The Masculine Virtues America Needs (2023).

96 

See, e.g., Hanna Rosin, The End of Men: And the Rise of Women (2012); Andrew Yarrow, Man Out: Men on the Sidelines of American Life (2018).

97 

See, e.g., Jennifer Homans, A Woman’s Place, N.Y. Times (Sept. 13, 2012), https://www.nytimes.com/2012/09/16/books/review/the-end-of-men-by-hanna-rosin.html.

98 

See, e.g., Philip N. Cohen, The “End of Men” Is Not True: What Is Not and What Might Be on the Road Toward Gender Equality, 93 B.U. L. Rev. 1159 (2013).

99 

See generally Reeves, supra note 8.

100 

See generallyEquimundo, supra note 14.

101 

In addition to the education and labor market ones noted above, deaths of despair, loneliness, and lack of purpose disproportionately plague men. See Reeves, supra note 8, at 60–72.

102 

See id. at x.

103 

Id.

104 

Id.

105 

Id. at 21. Reeves attributes girls’ greater success in education to their faster brain development. Id. at 8–11. But a constant cannot explain a variable. While girls have outperformed boys for decades, the gap between girls’ and boys’ grades has grown. See id. at 5–6. If kids’ brains have not changed in recent decades, then something else must have. One theory is that educational institutions changed to reward the skills that are valued in a service economy, which are disproportionately displayed by girls. Cf. Derek Thompson, Colleges Have a Guy Problem, The Atlantic (Sept. 14, 2021), https://www.theatlantic.com/ideas/archive/2021/09/young-men-college-decline-gender-gap-higher-education/620066/ (concluding that “some blend of variables—including economic, cultural, and biological factors—has created a scenario in which girls and women are more firmly attached to the education pipeline than men, in the U.S. and across the developed world”).

106 

Reeves, supra note 8, at 45–59; Raj Chetty et al., Race and Economic Opportunity in the United States: An Intergenerational Perspective, 135 Q.J. Econ. 711 (2020) (finding that Black men have far lower rates of intergenerational income mobility than white men, whereas no such race gap is found among women). Reeves observed that “[g]ender gaps in the labor markets are narrowing while race gaps widen,” Reeves, supra note 8, at 51, leading him to conclude that “[t]he deepest fissures in the labor market are not those between men and women” but “between white and Black workers and between the upper middle class and the middle class and working class,” id. at 18; compare MacKinnon, supra note 67, at 19 (noting in 1991 that “Black men, on average, make more than they [white women] do”), with Reeves, supra note 8, at 51 (“Black men now earn 14% less than white women and 33% less than white men.”). An intersectional perspective is crucial. For every Black man earning a college degree, there are two Black women, but Black men still earn higher wages than Black women. Id. at 50–52.

107 

See Erving Goffman, The Arrangement Between the Sexes, 4 Theory & Socy 301, 308 (1977) (explaining that “women may be defined as being less than men, but they are nonetheless idealized, mythologized, in a serious way through such values as motherhood, innocence, gentleness, sexual attractiveness, and so forth—a lesser pantheon, perhaps, but a pantheon nonetheless”).

108 

See Mary Anne Case, Disaggregating Gender from Sex and Sexual Orientation: The Effeminate Man in the Law and Feminist Jurisprudence, 105 Yale L.J. 1, 3 (1995) (discussing the “devaluation, in life and in law, of qualities deemed feminine”).

109 

See Reeves, supra note 8, at 13 (citing study that found that women earn 36% of STEM degrees).

110 

See Claudia Goldin, A Grand Gender Convergence: Its Last Chapter, 104 Am. Econ. Rev. 1091 (2014) (showing how the gender wage gap largely begins after women have children and how job structures like work flexibility can mediate this effect); Claire Cain Miller, The Gender Pay Gap Is Largely Because of Motherhood, N.Y. Times (May 13, 2017), https://www.nytimes.com/2017/05/13/upshot/the-gender-pay-gap-is-largely-because-of-motherhood.html (reporting on studies finding that the pay gap is largely due to motherhood).

111 

See Anna Brown, Despite Gains, Women Remain Underrepresented Among U.S. Political and Business Leaders, Pew Rsch. Ctr. (Mar. 20, 2017), https://www.pewresearch.org/short-reads/2017/03/20/despite-gains-women-remain-underrepresented-among-u-s-political-and-business-leaders/.

112 

See Jessica Grose, It’s Not Just Men and Boys Who Are Struggling Right Now, N.Y. Times (June 10, 2023), https://www.nytimes.com/2023/06/10/opinion/forgotten-girls-women.html (discussing research on increasing rates of “deaths of despair” from drugs, alcohol, or suicide among women without a college degree).

113 

See supra notes 47–54 and accompanying text.

114 

The argument here is not clean, because the age groupings in the feminist-identification data are under fifty and over fifty, whereas the wage gap data draws the line at age thirty. Still, age thirty is when the wage gap begins, but because the effects of the wage gap accumulate over time, it might not be until years later that they are felt significantly. And it is possible that an even stronger divide on feminist identification by age would be found if the line were drawn younger. More research is needed to investigate whether this is an age or cohort effect (or a combination of both).

115 

See sources cited supra note 110.

116 

See Barry Gewen, Irving Kristol, Godfather of Modern Conservatism, Dies at 89 (Sept. 18, 2009), https://www.nytimes.com/2009/09/19/us/politics/19kristol.html.

117 

When I asked students at one event about their experiences of gender in law school, one student responded that she hadn’t really felt the effects of gender until she was engaged and considering the impact of marriage and family on her career.

118 

See infra notes 189–193 and accompanying text.

119 

See, e.g., Dorothy Roberts, Spiritual and Menial Housework, 9 Yale J.L. & Feminism 51 (1997); Katherine Silbaugh, Turning Labor into Love: Housework and the Law, 91 Nw. Univ. L. Rev. 1 (1996); Peggie R. Smith, Regulating Paid Household Work: Class, Gender, Race and Agendas of Reform, 48 Am. U. L. Rev. 851 (1999). Even framing family carework as a “sacrifice” might be race or class biased, because for women in low-wage jobs, performing more carework might be a privilege they can scarcely afford. See Adrienne D. Davis, Straightening It Out: Joan Williams on Unbending Gender, 49 Am. U. L. Rev. 823, 842–43, 846 (2000) (“Engaging gender in its economic meanings requires considering how gender divides women”).

120 

See James Joyner, Men Can’t Have It All, Either, The Atlantic (June 26, 2012), https://www.theatlantic.com/business/archive/2012/06/men-cant-have-it-all-either/258890/.

121 

Some 59% of fathers and 53% of mothers say they wish they had taken more time off from work than they did following the birth or adoption of their child. See Juliana Menasce Horowitz et al., Americans Widely Support Paid Family and Medical Leave, but Differ over Specific Policies, Pew Rsch. Ctr. (Mar. 23, 2017), https://www.pewresearch.org/social-trends/2017/03/23/americans-widely-support-paid-family-and-medical-leave-but-differ-over-specific-policies/.

122 

See, e.g., Joan C. Williams et al., Cultural Schemas, Social Class, and the Flexibility Stigma, 69 J. Soc. Issues 209, 220–21 (2013) (discussing the stigma men face from their employers when they are involved in postbirth caregiving and act counter to gender-role expectations).

123 

See Rashawn Ray, Black Lives Matter at 10 Years: 8 Ways the Movement Has Been Highly Effective, Brookings (Oct. 12, 2022), https://www.brookings.edu/articles/black-lives-matter-at-10-years-what-impact-has-it-had-on-policing/.

124 

See id.

125 

See id.

126 

See Zackary Okun Dunivin et al., Black Lives Matter Protests Shift Public Discourse, 119 Proc. Nat’l Acad. Sci. e2117320119 (2022) (finding increases in public discourse about systemic racism and other Black emancipatory language).

127 

See Samantha Neal, Views of Racism as a Major Problem Increase Sharply, Especially Among Democrats, Pew Rsch. Ctr. (Aug. 19, 2017), https://www.pewresearch.org/short-reads/2017/08/29/views-of-racism-as-a-major-problem-increase-sharply-especially-among-democrats/.

128 

Id.

129 

Id.

130 

See Horowitz et al., supra note 121.

131 

See id.

132 

The transgender rights movement has been most closely associated with the gay and lesbian rights movements but has also at times overlapped or been allied with the women’s rights movement. SeeJami K. Taylor et al., The Remarkable Rise of Transgender Rights 15 (2018).

133 

See Steinmetz, supra note 16.

134 

See Taylor et al., supra note 132, at 9.

135 

See Adam Nagourney & Jeremy W. Peters, How a Campaign Against Transgender Rights Mobilized Conservatives, N.Y. Times (last updated Apr. 17, 2023), https://www.nytimes.com/2023/04/16/us/politics/transgender-conservative-campaign.html.

136 

Kim Parker et al., Americans’ Complex Views on Gender Identity and Transgender Issues, Pew Rsch. Ctr. (June 28, 2022), https://www.pewresearch.org/social-trends/2022/06/28/americans-complex-views-on-gender-identity-and-transgender-issues/ (finding that among Democrats younger than 30, 72% say someone can be a man or a woman even if that’s different from the sex they were assigned at birth, and 66% say society hasn’t gone far enough in accepting people who are transgender, with smaller majorities of Democrats 30 and older expressing these views).

137 

See Azeen Ghorayshi, Report Reveals Sharp Rise in Transgender Young People in the U.S., N.Y. Times (June 10, 2022), https://www.nytimes.com/2022/06/10/science/transgender-teenagers-national-survey.html (reporting that from 2017 to 2020, 1.4% of 13- to 17-year-olds and 1.3% of 18- to 24-year-olds were transgender, compared with about 0.5% of all adults—a significant rise from 2017).

138 

See infra notes 168–173 and accompanying text.

139 

See Young, supra note 65.

140 

Pamela Paul, The Far Left and Far Right Agree on One Thing: Women Don’t Count, N.Y. Times (July 3, 2022), https://www.nytimes.com/2022/07/03/opinion/the-far-right-and-far-left-agree-on-one-thing-women-dont-count.html.

141 

See supra notes 9–15 and accompanying text.

142 

Molly Fischer, The Real Backlash Never Ended, New Yorker (July 21, 2022), https://www.newyorker.com/books/second-read/the-real-backlash-never-ended.

143 

See id. (noting, inter alia, that “[t]he much anticipated election of the first woman as President gave way instead to the open misogyny of Donald Trump,” that “commentators fretted that #MeToo had gone too far nearly from the time #MeToo began,” and that “all decade long, conservative state legislatures across the country made abortion ever less accessible”).

144 

See Susan Faludi, Feminism Made a Faustian Bargain with Celebrity Culture. Now It’s Paying the Price, N.Y. Times (June 20, 2022), https://www.nytimes.com/2022/06/20/opinion/roe-heard-feminism-backlash.html (explaining how pop feminism has distracted us from “a more pernicious backlash, one that has never relented, one that has brought us the calamity of the Alito draft opinion,” one that has “never lost its force or focus,” and “its retribution has been and always will be meted out on the uncelebrated and unaffluent”).

145 

We Should All Be Feminists” T-Shirt, Dior, https://www.dior.com/en_us/fashion/products/213T03TA001_X0200-we-should-all-be-feminists-t-shirt-white-cotton-jersey-and-linen (last visited June 29, 2023).

146 

Faludi, supra note 144.

147 

See Fischer, supra note 142 (quoting Faludi).

148 

Stephanie Coontz: CCF Gender and Millennials Online Symposium: Overview, Council on Contemp. Fams. (Mar. 31, 2017), https://sites.utexas.edu/contemporaryfamilies/2017/03/30/coontz-overview/.

149 

See Fischer, supra note 142.

150 

See Ray, supra note 123.

151 

Cf. Robin L. West, From Choice to Reproductive Justice: De-Constitutionalizing Abortion Rights, 118 Yale L.J. 1394 (2009) (exposing Roe’s legal construction of abortion as a matter of privacy and the harms that flow therefrom); Note, Emily Otte, Toxic Secrecy: Non-Disclosure Agreements and #MeToo, 69 Univ. Kan. L. Rev. 545 (2021) (explaining secrecy as part of the problem of sexual misconduct and associated legal reforms, especially around nondisclosure agreements). On privacy, sex equality, and feminism more generally, see Jeannie Suk Gersen, Is Privacy a Woman?, 97 Geo. L.J. 485 (2009) (discussing the relationship between privacy and womanhood and highlighting divides within feminism on this issue).

152 

See Lewis, supra note 64 (noting that Emmett Till’s accuser was physically abused by her husband and that the circumstances under which she made her accusations were “coercive”).

153 

Suk, supra note 1, at 10–11.

154 

Id. at 11.

155 

Kate Manne, Down Girl: The Logic of Misogyny 19 (2017).

156 

We might expect the reverse. As we walk through the world, men’s overempowerment and women’s forbearance are at least partially the result of iterative individual choices, albeit through a choice set shaped and constrained by law and norms. By contrast, the law of misogyny is generally put in place by institutional mechanisms.

157 

Suk, supra note 1, at 9; accord id. at 62 (“The collective overentitlement by society to women’s forebearance flows from men’s overempowerment.”).

158 

Id. at 11.

159 

Cf. Faludi, supra note 9, at 41 (“Many in the women’s movement and in the mass media complain that men just ‘don’t want to give up the reins of power.’ But that would seem to have little applicability to the situations of most men, who individually feel not the reins of power in their hands but its bit in their mouths.”).

160 

Kristin Luker, Abortion and the Politics of Motherhood 193–94 (1985) (“While on the surface it is the embryo’s fate that seems to be at stake, the abortion debate is actually about the meaning of women’s lives.”).

161 

See id.; see also generally Spruill, supra note 43, at 1 (“There were two women’s movements in the 1970s: a women’s rights movement that enjoyed tremendous success, especially early in the decade, and a conservative women’s movement that formed in opposition and grew stronger as the decade continued,” and “[e]ach played an essential role in the making of modern American political culture.”).

162 

See, e.g., J. Scott Carter et al., Trends in Abortion Attitudes by Race and Gender: A Reassessment over a Four-Decade Period, 1 J. Socio. Rsch. 1, 2 (2009) (citing research supporting the conclusion that “[m]ost studies find gender alone to be a poor predictor of abortion attitudes”).

163 

There is a large literature on political polarization. For some overviews, see Paul Pierson & Eric Schickler, Madison’s Constitution Under Stress: A Developmental Analysis of Political Polarization, 23 Ann. Rev. Pol. Sci. 37 (2020); Ezra Klein, Why We’re Polarized (2020).

165 

See id.

166 

See Vicki Shabo, Polling Summary: In Build Back Better, Paid Family and Medical Leave Is One of the Most Popular Policies, New Am. (Nov. 10, 2021), https://www.newamerica.org/better-life-lab/blog/polling-summary-paid-family-and-medical-leave-is-one-of-the-most-popular-planks-in-the-build-back-better-agenda/.

167 

See id. Even when asking only about paid leave for mothers (not fathers) following the birth or adoption of a child (as compared with other family or health reasons for leave), more Democratic men (88%) than Republican women (79%) are in favor, and the latter are still more supportive than Republican men (70%). See Horowitz et al., supra note 121. For more on the gender divide among Republicans, see infra notes 201–202 and accompanying text.

168 

See infra notes 204–205 on the gender gap in partisan affiliation.

169 

See After Roe Fell: Abortion Laws by State, Ctr. Reprod. Rights, https://reproductiverights.org/maps/abortion-laws-by-state/ (last visited June 30, 2023); Molly Weston Williamson, The State of Paid Family and Medical Leave in the U.S. in 2023, Ctr. Am. Progress (Jan. 5, 2023), https://www.americanprogress.org/article/the-state-of-paid-family-and-medical-leave-in-the-u-s-in-2023/.

170 

See sources cited supra note 167.

171 

Suk, supra note 1, at 62.

172 

See Robin Abcarian, Column: She Wanted to Go Slow; He Wanted to Go Fast. She Told the World. Is Aziz Ansari a Victim or a Perpetrator?, L.A. Times, Jan. 17, 2018, https://www.latimes.com/local/abcarian/la-me-abcarian-ansari-20180117-story.html; Schleicher, supra note 70.

173 

See Wesley Yang, The Revolt of the Feminist Law Profs, Chron. of Higher Educ. (Aug. 7, 2019), https://www.chronicle.com/article/the-revolt-of-the-feminist-law-profs; Becca Rothfeld, Feminism and Kitsch, The Drift (Jan. 31, 2022), https://www.thedriftmag.com/feminism-and-kitsch/ (noting that #MeToo has been criticized for “its dogmatism, its disregard for due process, its fetishization of conspicuous performance of legible victimization, its allergy to rigor, and its narrow fixation on consent”).

174 

Paul, supra note 140; Goldberg, supra note 17. Some have highlighted the intersections between transgender rights and women’s rights. See Naomi Schoenbaum, The Supreme Court Victory for Transgender Women Is a Win for All Women, Slate (June 15, 2020), https://slate.com/news-and-politics/2020/06/supreme-court-transgender-women-aimee-stephens-victory.html (explaining how recognizing transgender rights fights sex stereotypes); Ria Tabacco Mar, Trans Rights Are Women’s Rights, ACLU (Mar. 17, 2023), https://www.aclu.org/news/lgbtq-rights/trans-rights-are-womens-rights (explaining that “advances in trans rights hold a specific promise for women’s liberation” because “tearing down laws and policies based on gender stereotypes … create[s] the opportunity for each of us to determine our own life story”).

175 

See Amy Allen, “Mommy Wars” Redux: A False Conflict, N.Y. Times (May 27, 2012), https://archive.nytimes.com/opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2012/05/27/the-mommy-wars-redux-a-false-conflict/ (explaining that “the debate over mothering is not just a conflict between feminists and women in general but rather a conflict internal to feminism itself”).

176 

This can be seen in law schools with the ubiquitous Women’s Law Association, which represents all women and nothing else. These groups tend to offer networking opportunities or other inoffensive programming, while other groups like those supporting reproductive rights take positions on the issues.

177 

Cf.Donald T. Critchlow, Phyllis Schlafly and Grassroots Conservatism: A Woman’s Crusade 8 (2005) (placing right ideology and especially women of the right within a “deeply rooted ideological sensibility that combines a libertarian espousal of the virtues of small government and individual responsibility with a faith in traditional values and divine moral authority”). As Professor Melinda Cooper has explained, these ideologies are intertwined, with neoliberal views placing responsibility not solely in the individual (rather than the state), but in the family. See generallyMelinda Cooper, Family Values: Between Neoliberalism and the New Social Conservativism (2017).

178 

See Horowitz et al., supra note 121.

179 

See id.

180 

See id.

181 

See Alberto Alesina et al., Why Doesn’t the United States Have a European-Style Welfare State?, 2 Brookings Papers on Econ. Activity 187, 187 (2001), https://www.brookings.edu/wp-content/uploads/2001/06/2001b_bpea_alesina.pdf (noting that “European governments redistribute income among their citizens on a much larger scale than does the U.S. government,” that “European social programs are more generous and reach a larger share of citizens,” and that “European tax systems are more progressive”).

182 

Suk, supra note 1, at 212.

183 

See Alberto Alesina et al., supra note 181, at 188–89 (explaining “American exceptionalism” on social welfare to Americans’ perception of the poor as undeserving and attributing this view to “troubled race relations,” which are “clearly a major reason for the absence of an American welfare state”); Heather McGhee, The Sum of Us: What Racism Costs Everyone and How We Can Prosper Together (2021) (arguing that America lacks state supports because of zero-sum racism: that gains to Black people come at the expense of whites).

184 

This can be seen even with the childcare funding that is and isn’t provided. See Kimberly J. Morgan, A Child of the Sixties: The Great Society, the New Right, and the Politics of Federal Child Care, 13 J. Pol’y Hist. 215 (2001) (showing how in the early 1970s, universal public daycare was defeated by the right’s critique of communal rather than family approaches and replaced with tax breaks for private daycare, whereas communal approaches like Headstart were appropriate for poor families).

185 

See id. at 215.

186 

Jack Rosenthal, President Vetoes Child Care Plan as Irresponsible, N.Y. Times (Dec. 10, 1971), https://timesmachine.nytimes.com/timesmachine/1971/12/10/90705630.html?pageNumber=1.

187 

Igor Bobic et al., Republicans Attack Child Care Funding as “Toddler Takeover,”HuffPost (Dec. 7, 2021, 6:19 PM), https://www.huffpost.com/entry/child-care-costs-democrats_n_61afd943e4b02df7c6ade143 (raising the specter of failures similar to the rollout of the Affordable Care Act).

188 

See Senate-Passed Inflation Reduction Act: Estimates of Budgetary and Macroeconomic Effects, Penn Wharton Budget Model (Aug. 12, 2022), https://budgetmodel.wharton.upenn.edu/issues/2022/8/12/senate-passed-inflation-reduction-act.

189 

See Julie Kashen & Kimberly Knackstedt, How Congress Got Close to Solving Child Care, Then Failed, The Century Found. (Sept. 15, 2022), https://tcf.org/content/commentary/how-congress-got-close-to-solving-child-care-then-failed/.

190 

See Suk, supra note 1, at 138 (documenting the successful framing of temperance as “everybody’s war”).

191 

Cf. Horowitz et al., supra note 121 (reporting that only 35% of Americans polled in 2017 thought paid family leave was an important priority, last on a list of twenty-one options).

192 

See Martin Gilens & Benjamin I. Page, Testing Theories of American Politics: Elites, Interest Groups, and Average Citizens, 12 Persps. on Pol. 564, 565 (2014) (finding that it is economic elites and business groups who get their policy preferences enacted in law). Many higher-income workers already have access to paid leave. See Horowitz et al., supra note 121. While Build Back Better’s childcare plan included universal pre-K and would have ultimately covered families at 250% of the state median income, more well-off families might not opt into these programs. See Kashen & Knackstedt, supra note 189.

193 

See generally Luker, supra note 160.

194 

Claire Cain Miller, Why the U.S. Has Long Resisted Universal Child Care, N.Y. Times (Aug. 15, 2019), https://www.nytimes.com/2019/08/15/upshot/why-americans-resist-child-care.html.

195 

See Horowitz et al., supra note 121.

196 

See id.

197 

See id.

198 

See id.

199 

See Richard Fry, Almost 1 in 5 Stay-at-Home Parents in the U.S. Are Dads, Pew Rsch. Ctr., https://www.pewresearch.org/short-reads/2023/08/03/almost-1-in-5-stay-at-home-parents-in-the-us-are-dads/. (Aug. 3, 2023) (finding that more than 80% of stay-at-home parents in the United States are moms).

200 

See generallyLuker, supra note 160.

201 

See West, supra note 151, at 1394 (arguing that “the right to abortion constitutionalized in Roe v. Wade is by some measure at odds with a capacious understanding of the demands of reproductive justice” because it “is fundamentally a negative right that rhetorically keeps the state out of the domain of family life,” and thus “the decision privatizes not only the abortion decision, but also parenting”).

202 

See Suk, supra note 1, at 99–100.

203 

See id. at 100 (“The care owed to the mother by the community includes an obligation on the part of the state to ensure that a pregnancy is not terminated because of existing material hardship or material hardship expected to occur after the birth. Similarly, if at all possible, disadvantages for the woman in her vocational training or work resulting from a pregnancy ought to be removed. In fulfillment of its obligation to protect unborn human life, the state must attend to problems likely to cause a pregnant woman or mother difficulty, and try, to the extent legally and realistically possible and justifiable, to alleviate or solve those problems.”). As Suk emphasizes, the Court recognized the duty for the state to support not only mothers, but “parents” more generally by “promot[ing] a child-friendly society.” Id. at 101.

204 

See generally West, supra note 151; Martha Albertson Fineman, The Autonomy Myth: A Theory of Dependency (2004).

205 

See Abby M. McCloskey, The GOP Failed Millennial Moms Like Me. But It Needs Us Now More Than Ever, Politico (July 15, 2022), https://www.politico.com/news/magazine/2022/07/15/republicans-losing-millennial-moms-essay-00045156.

206 

Suk, supra note 1, at 105.

207 

SeeRachel Treisman, States with the Toughest Abortion Laws Have the Weakest Maternal Supports, Data Shows, NPR, https://www.npr.org/2022/08/18/1111344810/abortion-ban-states-social-safety-net-health-outcomes (Aug. 18, 2022 6:00 AM ET) (“Mothers and children in states with the toughest abortion restrictions tend to have less access to health care and financial assistance, as well as worse health outcomes.”).

208 

There is a larger gender divide among Republicans than among Democrats, which has led some to question the quality of representation that Republican women receive from their own party. See Tiffany D. Barnes & Erin C. Cassese, American Party Women: A Look at the Gender Gap Within Parties, 70 Pol. Rsch. Q. 127 (2016) (based on survey data from 2012 finding that gender differences are more pronounced in the Republican than in the Democratic party, with Republican women reporting significantly more moderate views than their male counterparts, which the authors attribute to gender differences in beliefs about gender-based inequality and the appropriate scope of government); McCloskey, supra note 205. This raises old questions about whether some women align with the men in their lives rather than advocate for their own interests. See Goffman, supra note 107, at 308 (explaining that women are “separated from one another by the stake they acquire in the very organization which divides them [the heterosexual family],” that “a woman is likely to have (through the course of her life) a father, a husband, and sons,” and that “these males transmit to her enough of what they themselves possess or acquire to give her a vested interest” and can “plac[e] her in a coalition with her menfolk against the whole of the rest of the world”); Tea Pain, (@TeaPainUSA), X (June 5, 2023, 10:03 AM), https://twitter.com/TeaPainUSA/status/1665721008664330240 (“Behind every Republican man there’s a Republican woman selling out her sisterhood.”). This gender divide is also a race divide, as it is mostly white women who go right. See Angela Chapin, Of Course White Women Voted for Trump Again, The Cut (Nov. 17, 2020), https://www.thecut.com/2020/11/many-white-women-still-voted-for-trump-in-2020.html.

209 

See Lyman Stone & Brad Wilcox, Now Political Polarization Comes for Marriage Prospects, The Atlantic (June 11, 2023), https://www.theatlantic.com/ideas/archive/2023/06/us-marriage-rate-different-political-views/674358/.

210 

Suk, supra note 1, at 224–25, 230.

211 

All. for Fair Bd. Recruitment v. Weber, No. 2:21-CV-01951-JAM-AC, 2023 WL 3481146 (E.D. Cal. May 15, 2023) (addressing challenge to corporate board race requirement in state law); Meland v. Weber, No. 2:19-CV-02288-JAM-AC, 2021 WL 6118651 (E.D. Cal. Dec. 27, 2021) (addressing challenge to corporate board sex requirement in state law).

212 

Compare Meland, 2021 WL 6118651, at *6 (upholding gender quota over federal equal protection challenge because of differences between intermediate and strict scrutiny), with All. for Fair Bd. Recruitment, 2023 WL 3481146, at *1 (striking down race quota under federal Equal Protection Clause and 42 U.S.C. § 1981).

213 

See supra part I.

214 

See Suk, supra note 1, at 153–79.

215 

See Students for Fair Admissions, Inc. v. President & Fellows of Harvard Coll., 143 S. Ct. 2141 (2023).

216 

See Charlotte West, An Unnoticed Result of the Decline of Men in College: It’s Harder for Women to Get In, The Hechinger Rep. (Oct. 27, 2021), https://hechingerreport.org/an-unnoticed-result-of-the-decline-of-men-in-college-its-harder-for-women-to-get-in/.

217 

Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 306, 340 (2003); Gratz v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 244 (2003); Fisher v. Univ. of Tex., 579 U.S. 365 (2016).

218 

Students for Fair Admissions, 143 S. Ct. 2141.

219 

See Reeves, supra note 8, at 50.

220 

Schuller, supra note 59, at 10; see also Brent Scher, Gillibrand: If Lehman Brothers Were Lehman Sisters, We Would Have Avoided Financial Collapse, Wash. Free Beacon (May 15, 2018), https://freebeacon.com/politics/gillibrand-lehman-brothers-lehman-sisters-avoided-financial-collapse/ (quoting Senator Kirsten Gillibrand: “[I]f it wasn’t Lehman Brothers but Lehman Sisters, we might not have had the [2008] financial collapse.”).

221 

Suk, supra note 1, at 160–61.

222 

Id. at 161.

223 

See, e.g., David Stadelmann et al., Politicians and Preferences of the Voter Majority: Does Gender Matter?, 26 Econ. & Pols. 355 (2014) (finding that any gender differences in U.S. representatives voting for majority preferences are explained by party affiliation); Fernando Ferreira & Joseph Gyourko, Does Gender Matter for Political Leadership? The Case of U.S. Mayors, 112 J. Pub. Econ. 24 (2014) (finding no effect of gender of U.S. mayors on policy outcomes related to the size of local government).

224 

See Christina L. Boyd et al., Untangling the Causal Effects of Sex on Judging, 54 Am. J. Pol. Sci. 389 (2010) (observing gender effects in federal appellate decisions from 1978 to 2002 in one area of law, sex discrimination, but not for the body of law that Suk would consider misogynistic, such as abortion or sexual harassment). It would be worth replicating this study to see if the result with regard to sex discrimination holds with a more recent set of cases.

225 

See Fox 10 Staff & Associated Press, Groups Rally Outside Arizona Sen. Sinema’s Office to Address Child Care, Climate Change, Education, Fox 10 Phoenix (Oct. 19, 2021, 3:12 PM MST), https://www.fox10phoenix.com/news/groups-rally-outside-arizona-sen-sinemas-office-to-address-child-care-climate-change-education.

226 

For example, the leading Republican voice against the Pregnant Workers Fairness Act was a woman. See Press Release, Foxx Says H.R. 1065 “Is a Win for Big Government,” Comm. on Educ. & the Workforce (May 14, 2021), https://edworkforce.house.gov/news/documentsingle.aspx?DocumentID=407492 (“Education and Labor Committee Republican Leader Virginia Foxx (R-NC) spoke in opposition to the Pregnant Workers Fairness Act (H.R. 1065), which delivers an unnecessary blow to religious organizations”).

227 

See Suk, supra note 1, at 223.

228 

Id. at 224.

229 

Jan Luca Pletzer et al., Does Gender Matter? Female Representation on Corporate Boards and Firm Financial Performance—A Meta-Analysis, 10 PLoS ONE e0130005 (2015) (finding, in a meta-analysis of twenty peer-reviewed studies, that the correlation between the percentage of women on the board and firm performance was not statistically significant); Corinne Post & Kris Byron, Women on Boards and Firm Financial Performance: A Meta-Analysis, 58 Acad. Mgmt. J. 1546 (2015) (finding, in a meta-analysis of 140 studies with a combined sample of more than 90,000 firms from over 30 countries, a statistically significant but very small positive correlation between firms with more female directors and “accounting returns,” such as return on assets and return on equity).

230 

Consistent with the discrimination theory, if less-qualified men are preferred to more-qualified women, then a gender quota could increase the quality of board members.

231 

See Ron Lieber, Women May Be Better Investors Than Men. Let Me Mansplain Why, N.Y. Times (Oct. 29, 2021), https://www.nytimes.com/2021/10/29/your-money/women-investing-stocks.html (reviewing research to this effect).

232 

Suk, supra note 1, at 171.

233 

This example seems inconsistent with Suk’s definition of misogynistic law, which seems to require two parts, consistent with a theory of unjust enrichment: (1) men’s overempowerment (2) at women’s expense. This example seems to be lacking the latter.

234 

There is some mixed evidence of a glass cliff, which posits that women and minorities are more likely to be appointed to leadership positions when an organization or country are in crisis. See, e.g., Michelle K. Ryan et al., Politics and the Glass Cliff: Evidence that Women are Preferentially Selected to Contest Hard-to-Win Seats, 34 Psych. Women Q. 56 (2010).

235 

Cf. Samuel Moyn, Mark Lilla and the Crisis of Liberalism, Bos. Rev. (Feb. 27, 2018), https://www.bostonreview.net/articles/samuel-moyn-1968-and-crisis-liberalism/ (“Our economically neoliberal age has shaped many of the most exciting causes progressives have embraced in recent decades, helping to tilt them in an individualist and meritocratic direction.”) (citing “a feminism that honors the shattering of glass ceilings for elites but not the stagnation of the lives of middle-class and poor women”); Olúfẹ´mi O. Táíwò, Identity Politics and Elite Capture, Bos. Rev. (May 7, 2020), https://www.bostonreview.net/articles/olufemi-o-taiwo-identity-politics-and-elite-capture/ (arguing that “identity politics is the victim of elite capture—deployed by political, social, and economic elites in the service of their own interests, rather than in the service of the vulnerable people they often claim to represent”).

236 

Or not. See Greenhouse, supra note 12 (explaining how even women with resources may not be able to get abortions in restrictive states until their health deteriorates).

237 

See Táíwò, supra note 235.

238 

See Suk, supra note 1, at 225–33. Before making these changes, we’d probably also want to consider the effect on other policies we might care a lot about—economic stability, foreign relations, and so on.

239 

For a book-length treatment of concept of misalignment, see Nicholas Stephanopoulos, Aligning Election Law (forthcoming 2024).

240 

As Suk argues, this is true at the national level for abortion. See Suk, supra note 1, at 229, 291 n.58. It is not clear that abortion policy is misaligned with policy preferences at the state level. See Religious Landscape Study, Pew Rsch. Ctr. (2014), https://www.pewresearch.org/religion/religious-landscape-study/compare/views-about-abortion/by/state/ (showing views of abortion by state); Greenhouse, supra note 12 (noting that “[a]bout 40 percent of states have bans that make abortion illegal or functionally unavailable”). Nor is it clear the extent to which major laws on care, such as paid leave, are misaligned at the state level. See The State of Paid Family and Medical Leave in the U.S. in 2023, supra note 169 (cataloguing state paid leave laws).

241 

See infra notes 189–193 and accompanying text.

242 

See Tarunabh Khaitan, Political Parties in Constitutional Theory, inThe Constitutional Design of Elections and Parties (Tom Ginsburg et al. eds., forthcoming 2024).

243 

See Deborah Dinner, Strange Bedfellows at Work: Neomaternalism in the Making of Sex Discrimination Law, 91 Wash. U. L. Rev. 453 (2014); Naomi Schoenbaum, When Liberals and Conservatives Agree on Women’s Rights, Politico (Mar. 31, 2015), https://www.politico.com/magazine/story/2015/03/supreme-court-pregnancy-discrimination-coalition-116559/). Professor Dinner highlights how feminists forged alliances with the business community by relying on liberal individualist arguments and with anti-abortion activists by relying on “neomaternal” arguments, and she traces how the resulting policy compromises “continued to privatize the costs of reproduction.” See Dinner, supra, at 454. Today, these typically divergent groups are notably showing some alignment around the need for state support for care to achieve business success, reduce abortion, and promote sex equality. See infra notes 235–239 and accompanying text.

244 

McCloskey, supra note 205 (“Women have abortions for complicated and interrelated reasons, but the leading reason people cite—40% in a 2013 survey—is lack of financial security.”).

245 

See infra notes 196–200 and accompanying text.

246 

Suk, supra note 1, at 101.

247 

See, e.g., Dana Goldstein, In Post-Roe World, These Conservatives Embrace a New Kind of Welfare, N.Y. Times (Feb. 10, 2023), https://www.nytimes.com/2023/02/10/us/conservatives-child-care-benefits-roe-wade.html (reporting on “an influential group of conservative intellectuals” with “a full-spectrum family policy” that is “pro-life, but also supportive of those families as they are trying to raise kids” with “spending heavily on family benefits” and citing “a number of conservative members of Congress [who] have embraced new benefits for parents,” including senators Mitt Romney, Marco Rubio, Josh Hawley, and J.D. Vance); Oren Cass & Wells King, American Compass, The Family Income Supplemental Credit 1 (2021), https://americancompass.org/wp-content/uploads/2022/10/American_Compass-The_Family_Income_Supplemental_Credit-2021Feb18.pdf (proposing a per-child family benefit as a form of “reciprocal social insurance” and asking: “Will we [conservatives] support a major government program if it is pro-marriage, pro-family, pro-life, pro-work?”).

248 

Many Republican governors have focused on the business case for care, with, for example, Governor Michael Parsons stating, “Missouri businesses consistently rank the lack of child care options as a barrier to recruiting and retaining employees, and we have an opportunity to assist,” as he called for $78 million to increase child care subsidy rates. See Chabeli Carrazana, Democrats and Republicans Agree Child Care Is in Crisis. Why Can’t They Get a Bill Passed?, The 19th (Feb. 14, 2023), https://19thnews.org/2023/02/child-care-crisis-democrats-republicans-legislation/; AEI-Brookings Working Group on Paid Family Leave, AEI-Brookings Paid Family Leave Joint Blog Series (2017), https://www.aei.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/06/AEI-Brookings-Paid-Family-Leave-Joint-Blog-Series.pdf.

249 

See Sheri Berman, Why the U.S. Right Doesn’t Like Free Markets Anymore, Foreign Pol’y (Apr. 3, 2023), https://foreignpolicy.com/2023/04/03/us-right-economic-policy-gop-free-markets/ (citing “an emerging movement in right-wing U.S. politics that is trying to shift the Republican Party away from the embrace of free markets, business interests, and small government and toward an economic profile that … embrac[es] the government’s obligation to protect “workers, their families and communities, and the national interest”).

250 

See Carrazana, supra note 248 (“Republicans have faced some pressure to support families and children, particularly since federal abortion protections were eliminated when the Supreme Court overturned Roe v. Wade this summer.”); Joseph Zeballos-Roig, Conservatives Tossed Out Roe v. Wade. Now Some Are Pressuring the GOP to Soften Its Resistance to Financially Supporting Families or Risk a “Severe” Backlash, Bus. Insider (June 29, 2022, 12:16 PM), https://www.businessinsider.com/gop-child-benefits-family-support-backlash-abortion-2022-6.

251 

McCloskey, supra note 205; see also Goldstein, supra note 247 (noting that pro-family economic policy developing on the right is in part a response to restrictions on abortion rights).

252 

It is difficult to make a causal claim from Dobbs to the passage of the PWFA. In at least one way, it was made harder. Senate Majority Leader Chuck Schumer had set the bill for expedited consideration before Politico reported that the Court would overturn Roe v. Wade, but Democrats then put aside the bill to avoid the perception that it was the Democrats’ response to the news. See Eleanor Mueller, Crunch Time for Dems Is Holding Up Bipartisan Bill to Protect Pregnant Workers, Politico (Nov. 28, 2022, 1:36 PM), https://www.politico.com/news/2022/11/28/pregnant-workers-protections-bill-senate-00070734.

253 

See id.

254 

See id.

255 

Clint Rainey, Parents and Pregnant Workers Score Big Wins in the Omnibus Spending Package, Fast Co. (Dec. 22, 2022), https://www.fastcompany.com/90829078/pregnant-workers-fairness-pump-act-senate-vote-2023-spending-bill.

256 

Note the gendered language here, even though trans men chestfeed. See Naomi Schoenbaum, Unsexing Breastfeeding, 107 Minn. L. Rev. 139, 167 (2022). This might have made it an easier sell across the aisle. In contrast, the PWFA is written in gender-neutral language (“qualified employee affected by pregnancy, childbirth, or related medical conditions”), perhaps because it is modeled after the Americans with Disabilities Act. 42 U.S.C.A. § 2000 gg-1(2).

257 

See Chabeli Carrazana, The Full PUMP Act Is Now in Effect. Here’s What It Does for Lactating Parents, The 19th (Apr. 28, 2023), https://19thnews.org/2023/04/pump-act-what-it-does-lactating-workplace/ (citing ninety-two votes in favor in Senate).

258 

See Suk, supra note 1, at 103–05.

259 

Id. at 103.

260 

Id. at 218–21.

261 

See Deborah Dinner, Whither Liberalism After Misogyny?, Balkinization (May 6, 2023), https://balkin.blogspot.com/2023/05/whither-liberalism-after-misogyny.html.

262 

Oral argument tr. at 56, Dobbs v. Jackson Women’s Health Org., No. 19-1392 (U.S. Dec. 1, 2021), https://www.supremecourt.gov/oral_arguments/argument_transcripts/2021/19-1392_bq7d.pdf (Since “both Roe and Casey emphasize the burdens of parenting … [w]hy don’t the safe haven laws take care of that problem?”).

263 

See, e.g., Melissa Murray, The Only Mother on the Court, N.Y. Times (Dec. 2, 2021), https://www.nytimes.com/2021/12/02/opinion/coney-barrett-abortion-supreme-court.html (“It was a startling exchange—one that suggested that anti-abortion laws raise few constitutional issues in a world where adoption is available to those who wish to avoid parenthood.”).

264 

Ultimately, Germany provides a relatively robust right to abortion, including state payment for it—another reason why the German approach seems unlikely to translate to at least parts of the United States. In Germany, no amount of state support is sufficient to bar abortion in many circumstances, including those performed for the life or health (including mental health) of the mother, for a fetal abnormality, or for a pregnancy that is due to rape. Suk, supra note 1, at 104. These are just the reasons for lawful abortions that the state is required to fund, but women can still get unfunded “unlawful” abortions without penalty. See id.

265 

SeeJamal Greene, How Rights Went Wrong: Why Our Obsession with Rights Is Tearing America Apart 115 (2021) (arguing that abortion became less politically divisive in Germany because that country’s approach to abortion “recogniz[ed] multiple and competing constitutional rights,” whereas the issue became more politically divisive in the United States because of “American courts’ insistence on choosing between rights—their systematic failure to account for and mediate rights conflicts”).

266 

See id. at 124 (explaining how Roe “eroded the political center [of abortion politics], making compromise more difficult”).

267 

See Katrin Bennhold, In Sweden, Men Can Have It All, N.Y. Times (June 9, 2010), https://www.nytimes.com/2010/06/10/world/europe/10iht-sweden.html.

268 

See Ellen Barry, In Sweden’s Preschools, Boys Learn to Dance and Girls Learn to Yell, N.Y. Times (Mar. 24, 2018), https://www.nytimes.com/2018/03/24/world/europe/sweden-gender-neutral-preschools.html.

269 

See Bennhold, supra note 267 (reporting significant increase in paternal leave-taking in Sweden and Germany after robust leave policies were enacted).

270 

See id.

Author notes

*

William Wallace Kirkpatrick Dean’s Research Professor of Law, George Washington University School of Law. I thank Juliana Chang, Martha Minow, David Schleicher, and Laura Weinrib for extremely helpful comments and Kristin Luker for inspiring the title of this review with her important 1985 book, Abortion and the Politics of Motherhood. For above-and-beyond research assistance, I thank Juliana Chang. For excellent editorial feedback, I thank Grace Cho.

This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License, which permits you to copy and redistribute in any medium or format, for non-commercial use only, provided that the original work is not remixed, transformed, or built upon, and that appropriate credit to the original source is given. For a full description of the license, please visit https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/legalcode.