The United States regularly seeks to promote the liberal norms of respect for human rights and deference to civilian authority in the militaries that it trains. Yet norm-abiding behavior often does not follow from liberal foreign military training. Existing explanations ascribe norm violations either to insufficient socialization or to interest misalignment between providers and recipients. One reason violations occur is because liberal training imparts conflicting norms. How do militaries respond when they confront the dilemma of conflict between the liberal norms of respect for human rights and civilian control of the military? The U.S. policy expectation is that trained militaries will prioritize human rights over obedience to civilian authorities. But when liberal norms clash, soldiers fall back on a third norm of cohesion, which refers to the bonds that enable military forces to operate in a unified, group- and missionoriented way. Cohesion functions as both a military norm (particularly at the individual level) and an interest (particularly at the institutional level). If a military prioritizes cohesion, then it will choose the path that best serves its organization, which may entail violating human rights, civilian control, or both. An exploration of the effects of norm conflict on military attitudes among the Armed Forces of Liberia uses an experiment embedded in a survey to probe the theory. Results provide preliminary evidence that norm conflict weakens support for human rights and democracy. Results are strongest among soldiers with more U.S. training.

On April 14, 1979, the “rice riots” broke out in Monrovia, Liberia. Several thousand protestors took to the streets in frustration and desperation over a government proposal to increase the price of rice, a food staple that most Liberians relied on for subsistence. As demonstrators marched toward the president's mansion, President William Tolbert ordered soldiers to fire into the crowd.1 Over forty protestors were killed in the ensuing chaos. Although the soldiers obeyed Tolbert's order, the command to shoot their fellow Liberians sparked deep animosity and contributed to a bloody coup the following year.2

These rice riots illustrate the conflict that can occur between the two liberal norms of respect for human rights and civilian control of the military. When political leaders order militaries to harm the population, these two norms enter into conflict. Militaries are expected to obey political leaders, and they are also expected to protect populations. When the rice riots broke out in 1979, the United States had been training the Liberian military for eighteen years. The goal was to create a disciplined, democratic force, and this meant training the military to both respect human rights and obey civilian authority.3 Tolbert's order pitted these norms against each other, presenting the military with a dilemma. This article examines how norm conflict drives militaries to prioritize cohesion instead of either liberal norm.

Liberal great powers fail to acknowledge this dilemma as they seek to spread liberal norms globally through foreign military training. Foreign military training is a flexible form of security assistance that seeks to modify recipient militaries' behavior by increasing warfighting capacity and transmitting a set of professional norms or ideas about standards of appropriate behavior.4 Norm content and emphasis varies across providers, time, and space. For liberal democratic providers such as the United States, two of the most salient norms are civilian control of the military and respect for human rights.5 The theory and empirics that follow focus on the United States as a key liberal power. While the argument applies to all liberal providers, and all great powers use training as part of their security assistance repertoire, the United States is the largest such provider.6 In 2019, for example, the United States spent nearly $905 million to train over 71,000 military students from 157 states.7

Today, the United States ostensibly promotes these two liberal norms as a primary foreign policy objective to nearly half of all states that receive its military training.8 A mix of idealistic and strategic motives explains this emphasis. Imparting liberal norms is partially bound up in Western states' efforts to promote global democracy after the Cold War, which included providing security assistance to liberalize militaries.9 But imparting liberal norms is also strategic. Shaping how partner militaries think is an inexpensive way to gain voluntary policy compliance.10 Training also helps to inculcate a shared military identity, common skills, and communication, indirectly strengthening a third norm of cohesion. Training can thus reduce the costs of security management by creating more competent, cohesive, disciplined, and loyal partners.11

The empirical record, however, suggests that training often fails to deliver on its promise of liberal norm transmission. Security assistance frequently produces noncompliant, norm-violating militaries that conduct coups and abuse human rights.12 Policymakers and scholars offer divergent explanations for these shortcomings. Some suggest that norm violations result from insufficient investment in training or inadequate emphasis on norm socialization.13 Most scholars, conversely, favor rationalist arguments that point to interest misalignment between providers and recipients.14 While these arguments ascribe norm violations to different mechanisms, they share a common assumption that socialization never occurred in the first place. This assumption, however, overlooks the dilemma that arises when these two liberal norms conflict.

In this article, I argue that norm conflict weakens military support for both liberal norms, thus creating the conditions under which perverse behavioral outcomes can occur despite socialization. The implicit expectation in U.S. policy, should norm conflict arise, is that militaries will privilege human rights over civilian authority, temporarily defying civilian leaders to protect the higher order of rights “rooted in natural law.”15 This expectation rests on the assumptions that trained militaries share this rank-ordering, will easily choose human rights over civilian control, and that norm conflict will not damage either norm.16 If anything, conflict might clarify norms and promote socialization.17

I contend that these assumptions rest on shaky foundations. Rather than strengthening liberal norms, I argue that conflict between norms makes them less salient and undermines their power to restrain decision-making.18 Norm conflict invites cost-benefit calculations and creates openings to pursue self-interest.19 Conflict thus produces incentives for militaries to strategically choose among norms in an effort to satisfy both norms and interests. When this happens, they are more likely to fall back on the third norm of cohesion, a norm that is tied to interests. Fraught domestic crises that pit liberal norms against each other may further increase the salience of cohesion. Rank-ordering happens, but not in the direction that the United States expects.

If a military prioritizes cohesion, then it will choose the path that best serves its organization, which may entail violating human rights, civilian control, or both. I thus seek to explain shifts in military support for liberal norms rather than to predict specific instances of disobedience or abuse in any given political context. I examine the conditions under which norm violations become possible and shed light on the links between socialization efforts, attitudes, and ultimate behavior.20 Norm conflict, I argue, can weaken liberal norms and frustrate socialization over the long run.21 My study explores the determinants of decision-making to explain how cohesion comes to occupy a central place in military concerns, over and above liberal normative considerations.22

As a plausibility probe of these competing claims, I use experimental evidence from a survey of the Armed Forces of Liberia (AFL). The United States rebuilt the AFL after Liberia's civil war ended in 2003. U.S. trainers heavily emphasized liberal norms, making Liberia a most-likely case for norm socialization. The survey experiment presents soldiers with a scenario in which a political leader orders the military to put down protests with force, pitting the norms of civilian control and respect for human rights against each other. The scenario thus provides an experimental “stress test” of competing norms.23 Additionally, I conducted over fifty elite-level interviews with U.S. officials, trainers, and Liberian military officers.

My research indicates that when soldiers hear this scenario, their willingness to choose between conflicting liberal norms decreases, and they express more concern for maintaining cohesion. Liberal training conditions this response but in unexpected ways: Soldiers with more U.S. training express less willingness to prioritize human rights and are less supportive of democratic norms.24 Importantly, the survey evidence also shows that soldiers with more U.S. training express the strongest support for liberal norms in the absence of norm conflict, undermining the alternative argument that socialization never happened.

These findings shed light on a pathway by which norm violations can happen even in the presence of socialization. By highlighting a previously unrecognized dilemma in the model of civil-military relations that liberal powers seek to export, I contribute to studies that explore contradictions and complexity in military norms,25 as well as studies that examine how norms and interests interact and shape behavior.26 Liberal great powers typically consider the norms of civilian control of the military and respect for human rights to be mutually reinforcing, even though they often are not, particularly in weak democracies. My findings suggest that norm conflicts can have a corrosive effect on military support for liberal norms by incentivizing militaries to privilege a third norm of cohesion. This outcome indicates that the assumptions underlying a major component of U.S. foreign policy may be flawed, and it suggests the need to fundamentally reevaluate the approach to norm transmission.

The remainder of this article is organized as follows. First, I describe liberal powers' efforts to impart ideas about civilian control of the military and respect for human rights to the militaries that they train. Second, I lay out my argument about the implications of conflict between these two liberal norms—situating it within the literatures on norm contestation, psychology, and sociology—and I generate testable hypotheses. Third, I discuss research design, including case selection. The fourth section presents the experimental results and explores mechanisms that aid in interpreting the results. I conclude with a discussion of implications for theory and policy.

Since the end of the Cold War, foreign military training by liberal democratic powers has increasingly focused on promoting norms.27 British policy, for example, has stated that “support to build the capacity of security forces must be matched with efforts to build accountability, legitimacy and respect for human rights.”28 Similarly, Canada's Military Training and Cooperation Program seeks to “promote Canadian democratic principles, the rule of law and the protection of human rights.”29 The United States likewise emphasizes human rights and civilian control of the military. The Barack Obama administration articulated a goal of U.S. security sector assistance as promoting “universal values, such as good governance, transparent and accountable oversight of security forces, rule of law … and respect for human rights.”30 As of 2017, U.S. law requires that all efforts to build foreign military capacity include training on “observance of and respect for the law of armed conflict, human rights and fundamental freedoms, the rule of law, and civilian control of the military.”31

Importantly, the United States emphasizes norms training in different regions. I find that this training tends to occur in places where policymakers believe that more liberal and professional militaries are key to long-term political stability and democracy, or where they need to couch security assistance in liberal values to sell U.S. involvement.

Adherence to the liberal norms of human rights and civilian control of the military were primary foreign policy objectives of U.S. training in sixty-two states, as depicted in figure 1.32 Almost 90 percent of states in Africa receive training on these norms each year. This prominence suggests that the United States uses norms training in those places where it would prefer to delegate security management and avoid intervention.33 Because military training also imparts human capital and technical skills, the United States hopes to simultaneously create more competent and more liberal armed forces, capable of providing security while avoiding repressive and corrupt behavior that can jeopardize stability.

Recipients of U.S. Military Norms Training in 2019

Figure 1.
Recipients of U.S. Military Norms Training in 2019

SOURCE: Data are from the Department of Defense and Department of State, Foreign Military Training and DoD Engagement Activities of Interest, 2019–2020.

NOTE: The dark-shaded states represent recipients of U.S. military norms training in 2019.

Figure 1.
Recipients of U.S. Military Norms Training in 2019

SOURCE: Data are from the Department of Defense and Department of State, Foreign Military Training and DoD Engagement Activities of Interest, 2019–2020.

NOTE: The dark-shaded states represent recipients of U.S. military norms training in 2019.

Close modal

Foreign military training is a preferred tool to impart norms.34 Whereas other forms of security assistance such as arms transfers may come with conditions to modify behavior or extract policy concessions, training seeks to change military preferences primarily through socialization. Training offers opportunities for teaching and persuasion, which can be powerful in shaping professional worldviews.35 “Professional training,” according to Martha Finnemore and Kathryn Sikkink, “actively socializes people to value certain things above others.”36 Trainers use their expertise, information, and resources to promote certain norms while discouraging others.37 Consistent messaging plays a role; as a military instructor tasked with training the new AFL put it, “You tell somebody something long enough, they'll believe it. You have to capture their mind for their body to follow.”38 Additionally, training offers opportunities for interpersonal interaction and relationship-building, which may help foster shared preferences.39

Training takes diverse forms. Military officers attending regional seminars or courses in U.S. military schools are exposed to liberal norms through programs such as the International Military Education and Training program.40 Tactical training can also include a normative component. For example, when the U.S. military trains African counterterrorism forces, they spend up to a week on human rights education in the context of targeting practices.41 Finally, trainers try to tailor their application of norms to the local context. In Liberia, for example, Michigan National Guard advisers explained human rights in terms such as “it's wrong to shoot individuals with 50-caliber bullets.”42

cultivating cohesion

But U.S. training imparts more than liberal norms—it also helps to cultivate cohesion, which refers to the bonds that enable military forces to operate in a unified, group- and mission-oriented way.43 The imperative to preserve these bonds functions as a norm that motivates soldiers to prioritize loyalty and commitment to their unit, the military, and shared goals. It is almost always in the individual's best interest to pursue cohesion, even though doing so can sometimes require self-sacrifice for either the group or certain strategic goals.44 Indeed, at the military institutional level, cohesion represents a core interest. “Cohesion, discipline, and morale within the corps” are key to the military's self-preservation as well as its ability to secure other organizational interests.45 As David Pion-Berlin et al. note, “preservation of institutional unity has always been the centerpiece of military interests.”46

Cohesion functions as both a military norm (particularly at the individual level) and an interest (particularly at the institutional level). Because this article's theory and tests focus on individual decision-making, I treat cohesion as a norm, albeit one that is aligned to interests in ways that are difficult to fully separate.47

Cohesion reflects societal and political factors as well as military factors such as operational practices and training.48 This article focuses on training, which fosters a common military identity, skills, and modes of communication that help to create cohesion over time.49 Cohesion is not taught as a principle to follow (e.g., “do not abuse civilians”); rather, it is instilled through training and practices that emphasize solidarity, shared identity, and teamwork to accomplish goals. Over time, this emphasis on solidarity, shared identity, and teamwork contributes to a sensemaking process through which cohesion emerges as a norm. In Liberia, for example, trainers frequently used competition between small groups to both foster team-building and hold squad members accountable to one another.50 AFL officers described basic training as a “culture shock”51 and that training ideas ranged from “intriguing” to “goofy,” such as doing push-ups as punishment for not shining boots. Eventually, however, the need for discipline and teamwork began to make sense to the trainees.52 Although U.S. training does not explicitly seek to teach cohesion in the same way that it teaches liberal norms, it increases capacity for unified action, strengthens organizational interests, and it indirectly imparts a third norm of cohesion.

explaining norm violations

The return on investment for imparting liberal norms often appears meager. Evidence suggests that U.S.-trained militaries launch coups, subvert the rule of law, and oppress the people they are supposed to protect.53 Infamously, the U.S. Army's School of the Americas—created in 1946 to educate Latin American military officers on “the virtues of democratic civilian control over the armed forces”—produced a generation of coup-makers instead.54

The international relations literature offers contrasting explanations for norm violations. One set of arguments suggests that the problem is insufficient training or attention to norms.55 As the head of U.S. Africa Command said after U.S.-trained soldiers were implicated in the 2012 coup d'état in Mali: “We didn't spend, probably, the requisite time focusing on values, ethics, and military ethos.”56 In this view, norm violations reflect a failure to successfully socialize militaries to new norms in the first place. A second set of arguments, the rationalist perspective, uses a principal-agent framework to explain recipient behavior.57 Providers function as principals that arm and equip weaker states to act as agents on their behalf, but divergent priorities and asymmetric information lead to agent-shirking and noncompliance.58 These studies suggest that norm transmission, if attempted at all, will be anemic compared with the powerful interests that motivate behavior.

Both explanations oversimplify decision-making in different but problematic ways. The first perspective, which emphasizes socialization, discounts the power of interests in motivating behavior. It also fails to consider which norms will exercise the most influence over decision-making. Conversely, the rationalist perspective discounts the role of norms in shaping preferences and constraining behavior. In contrast, I treat military decision-making as the joint product of norms and interests, contributing to scholarship that examines the conditions under which utilitarian or normative considerations govern decision-making.59 Next, I look at how conflict between two liberal norms weakens support for those norms and opens a pathway for other, more utilitarian norms to dominate.60

I argue that in moments of norm conflict, militaries will prioritize cohesion over the two liberal norms of respect for human rights and civilian control of the military. My argument begins with the premise that norms mediate decision-making because they serve as social constraints that people follow for psychological and sociological reasons. Nonconformity with group norms can lead to social sanctions and shaming;61 violating personal beliefs can affect self-esteem.62 People thus forgo pursuit of naked self-interest to maintain their positive self-image and social standing. Similarly, collective actors comply with norms to legitimize their behavior and minimize resistance from other actors.63

Determining which norms to follow, however, is not always clear. There are many different norms with potentially countervailing implications for behavior—what Paul Kowert and Jeffrey Legro call the “ubiquity” of norms problem.64 The problem of conflicting norms is well-noted in the literatures on law, sociology, and international relations.65 For example, the international relations literature has explored the tension between the norm of state sovereignty and humanitarian norms such as the “responsibility to protect.”66 Moreover, following certain norms may come at a cost to other values, even if the decision is not framed as a choice between them.67 As Jon Elster puts it, “In some contexts, following the lodestar of outcome-oriented rationality is easy compared with finding one's way in a jungle of social norms.”68

Surprisingly, scholars and policymakers have neglected the problem of norm conflict that is at the heart of liberal civil-military relations.69 In the liberal formulation, the norms of human rights and civilian authority are mutually reinforcing. The empirical record underscores this assumption: where the United States provides norms training, it typically bundles both norms as a package deal. Almost every country in sub-Saharan Africa, for example, receives military training on both norms every year (see figure 1).

Liberalism's inherent support for civilian control of the military assumes that this civilian control represents the best way to protect both human rights and democracy.70 Although these two norms usually are mutually reinforcing in strong democracies, this assumption may fail in precisely the places where norms training is most prevalent: weak democracies and fragile states. Such states often lack strong legal institutions to rein in executive leaders, and their militaries often lack robust military justice systems to establish the legality of orders. Despite Eric Nordlinger's warning that “liberalism's abiding and indiscriminate preference for civilian control is a debatable issue,” the problem of norm conflict in liberal civil-military relations has avoided scrutiny.71

When situations arise with conflicting implications for behavior, militaries face consequential choices without clear answers. The following section examines competing predictions about the effects of norm conflict on military decision-making.

military responses to norm conflict

How will militaries respond to the conflicting norms of respect for human rights and civilian control? Although U.S. policy discourse rarely broaches the problem of norm conflict, there is an implicit expectation, should contradictions arise, that the military will temporarily prioritize human rights rather than defer to civilian authority. This expectation derives from liberal understandings of natural law; as the Defense Department notes, “the English philosopher John Locke believed that human rights, not governments, came first in the natural order of things.”72 Given that orders to abuse human rights violate natural law, the military can justifiably disobey such presumably illegal orders. This understanding reflects a long tradition in U.S. military norms, which holds that military personnel must disobey orders that are “manifestly illegal.”73 Less clear is whether officers should obey orders that they perceive to be immoral but not necessarily illegal.74 Still, the preference ordering is clear: people first, governments second. If norms conflict, the military should choose human rights over civilian control.

There is some evidence that the United States tries to impart this rank-ordering of norms. In testimony before U.S. Congress, the commander of U.S. Africa Command said, “We recognize building legitimate defense institutions is critical for African governments that prioritize the security of their citizens over that of the state” (emphasis added).75 Evidence from my interviews suggests that U.S. officers at least occasionally socialize other militaries to follow only legal orders. For example, the AFL's top officers, intensively trained by the United States, said that the United States prepared the AFL to be “very bold” in telling political leaders when they were asking the military to do something they could not or should not do. In contrast, one officer said, other actors in Liberia lacked “courage” to defy illegal orders.76

The U.S. policy expectation that militaries will choose human rights rests upon two assumptions. First, it assumes that choosing between conflicting norms is easy. At the individual level, people are presumed to choose between values with relative ease. Although people may resist substituting deeply held values for less important ones, when the choice is between two important values, they can frame the problem as a “tragic tradeoff” and avoid damage to self-esteem or social standing.77 Moreover, the choice of which norm to privilege should be facilitated by the presence of a blueprint for prioritization (“people first”).

The second assumption is that norm conflict will not damage either norm. Rank-ordering norms in a crisis should not make the violated norm any less salient; rather, it is temporarily downgraded to accommodate the more important principle in that moment.78 If anything, the process of adjudicating between the norms might strengthen them both. Research on norm contestation suggests that norm conflicts can drive norm violations, but these violations ultimately strengthen socialization in the long term by clarifying ambiguity and resolving future norm conflict.79

Insomuch as liberal powers think about other norms and interests beyond these two central liberal norms, they treat them as unproblematic for crisis decision-making. Norm conflicts are not viewed as problematic for cohesion; if anything, cohesion should make militaries more unified in doing the right thing. Properly socialized military personnel, according to the liberal training logic, should be willing to make costly choices even as liberal normative considerations should continue to guide decisions.

Counter to U.S. policy expectations, I argue that these assumptions rest on shaky foundations. Instead, when liberal norms clash, military members fall back on a third norm of cohesion that is consistent with group interests. Rank-ordering of norms does happen but not in the direction that the United States expects. Rather than choosing human rights over civilian control, military decision-making is less likely to be constrained by either liberal norm in favor of cohesion.

Norm conflicts make it more likely for soldiers to fall back on cohesion in at least two ways. First, conflict makes the contested norms less salient during the crisis. The assumption that norm conflict does not adversely affect norms misses the alternative possibility that it makes them easier to ignore instead.80 Scholarship has shown that norm conflicts can weaken support for prohibition norms in warfare, such as norms against the use of chemical weapons.81 Contestation eliminates the “taken for granted” quality of norms; once challenged, norms may no longer “operate as either a focal point for mutual expectations or as a naturalized guide for behavior.”81 Conflict between liberal norms invites cost-benefit calculations because the norms are no longer unquestionable. It can be costly to choose between either disobeying leaders and protecting civilians or, conversely, obeying leaders and brutalizing civilians. Weighing costs and benefits thus creates incentives to instrumentally follow other norms that best serve soldiers' interests. Militaries have another such norm as recourse: cohesion, which is neither inherently liberal nor conflictive with their self-interest.

Second, liberal norm conflicts are often situations that also threaten cohesion. Crises that pit political leaders against the population, with the military in the middle, are fraught situations that can threaten cohesion. Disagreement over whether to obey orders may create fears of fissures in the ranks.83 Individuals may be reluctant to make choices that they perceive as potentially divisive and harmful to cohesion. Indeed, insights from the literature on military obedience show that militaries often prioritize cohesion when deciding whether to obey or defect during crises.84 I argue that psychological dynamics explain why cohesion dominates decision-making. Structurally, cohesion becomes more salient even as the clashing liberal norms become less salient.

Prioritizing cohesion offers military members a way to behave normatively while protecting their interests and preserving the organization. Contrary to a purely instrumental logic under which norms are cast aside as soon as they clash with interests, people still try to justify their actions in normative terms.85 But people can also choose strategically among norms. Because cohesion satisfies both interests and norms, I argue that it is more likely to be selected in a crisis. This dynamic explains both the ascendance of cohesion and interests to the forefront of decision-making and the descendance, even if temporary, of regard for liberal norms. This dynamic does not mean that cohesion is fundamentally at odds with liberal norms, nor does it automatically predict norm violations. Rather, conflict between liberal norms creates the conditions that make violations possible. By vitiating liberal normative restraints, military crisis decision-making will be driven by whatever best serves cohesion, which may involve violating human rights, civilian control, or both norms. While this argument seeks to explain changes in support for norms rather than specific behavioral outcomes, I consider implications for behavior below.

Finally, several factors may exacerbate norm conflict. First, the liberal preference ordering of “people first, governments second” is not always communicated clearly in practice. U.S.-trained militaries are not taught to choose human rights nearly as systematically as the rhetoric suggests. One reason for the disconnect between theory and practice is that policymakers may deny the possibility of norm tradeoffs between human rights and civilian control because of the tendency to engage in wishful thinking.86 In private conversations, U.S. military officers have described this potential for norm conflict as a “conundrum” or “third rail” in security assistance, admitting that they try to avoid addressing it altogether. When civilians order the military to do things that are illegal, U.S. advice tends to be inchoate, offering “fifty-four different answers” depending on the situation.87

Another reason for the disconnect may be divergent preferences between the U.S. military and its own civilian leaders; the Defense Department's public Lockean position has been undercut in unofficial presidential rhetoric.88 Bureaucratic silos may also play a role: Different entities conduct U.S. training on civil-military relations and on human rights.

Second, militaries with histories of factionalism or civil war may be more prone to prioritizing cohesion. Not only might these militaries be more sensitive to the risk of internal rifts, but they often lack robust military justice systems and doctrines to evaluate the legality of orders and provide guidance for action. Illustrative evidence points to this kind of sensitivity in the Liberia case. When asked in the survey what the Liberian military's motto (“A Force for Good”) meant to them, many soldiers' responses emphasized cohesion: “a force that can't ever be factionalized,” “united,” and “here to stay.”

hypotheses

I predict that norm conflict will weaken support for liberal norms, undermining their robustness by making them less salient in crises.89 Rather than prompting soldiers to choose human rights over civilian control, as the United States expects, moments of norm conflict are more likely to undermine support for both norms and prompt militaries to select a third norm, cohesion, which is consistent with their interests. This argument produces the following hypotheses:

H1: Moments of norm conflict reduce soldiers' willingness to prioritize human rights over civilian control.

H2: Moments of norm conflict reduce soldiers' support for democratic norms.

H3: Moments of norm conflict increase soldiers' prioritization of cohesion.

In contrast, U.S. policy expectations predict that soldiers experiencing norm conflict will prioritize human rights. Although this choice temporarily rankorders human rights over civilian control, norm conflicts may enhance—or at least not undermine—support for democratic norms. This outcome suggests the following hypotheses:

H4: Moments of norm conflict increase soldiers' willingness to prioritize human rights over civilian control.

H5: Moments of norm conflict increase soldiers' support for democratic norms.

Finally, I consider how liberal foreign military training might condition how militaries respond to norm conflict. On the one hand, insomuch as training promotes liberal norms and actively socializes a norm hierarchy of “people first,” then U.S. training should strengthen the propensity to prioritize human rights. On the other hand, training cultivates a common identity and solidarity at the individual level, increases military autonomy, and indirectly bolsters organizational interests. Should norm conflict arise, training may strengthen cohesion, at the expense of liberal norms. These alternatives suggest two final hypotheses:

H6a: Soldiers with U.S. training will be less likely to prioritize human rights or support democratic norms in moments of norm conflict.

H6b: Soldiers with U.S. training will be more likely to prioritize human rights and support democratic norms in moments of norm conflict.

scope conditions

Before turning to the empirical analyses, I consider the conditions under which norm conflicts are more likely to occur and where their effects may be more severe. The first two scope conditions are regime type and institutional strength—the likelihood and severity of norm conflict may increase in weak democracies. First, democratic or pseudo-democratic90 states typically at least attempt (or feign) to adhere to both norms. These are also the states that are most likely to receive norms training, which means that the seeds of the dilemma are present. Other mechanisms can drive norm violations, but for norm conflict to occur, both liberal norms must be present—otherwise there is no contradiction. Further, sometimes the preferences of the government and the population diverge in new or weak democracies, and these divergences may prompt elites to use the military against the public.91

Moreover, such states typically have weak institutions and fragile rule of law. Strong courts, legislatures, and military justice systems both constrain leaders from making illegal orders and hold militaries accountable. These institutional restraints are one reason why norm conflicts surface less frequently in established democracies and, if they do, why their effects tend to be less severe. For example, when U.S. President Donald Trump suggested in 2018 that soldiers would shoot any migrants who threw rocks along the Mexican border, military leaders and analysts quickly emphasized that such a disproportionate response would be illegal.92 Even if norm conflicts vitiate normative considerations, institutions restrain behavior. The U.S. Uniform Code of Military Justice, for example, provides legal guidance for military decision-making. Robust legal institutions capable of adjudicating between such conflicts, however, are almost always missing in weak states where most norms training occurs.

The military's orientation toward external defense or internal security may also affect the likelihood of norm conflict and the severity of its effects. Militaries tasked with law enforcement or regime protection are far more likely to face crisis scenarios where norm conflicts can surface.93 Conversely, established democracies generally avoid using the military for domestic law enforcement. Tension between respect for human rights and civilian control of the military would not seem as remote a possibility in the United States if the military were used for law enforcement, a problem avoided by the 1878 Posse Comitatus Act, which banned use of the military in policing functions. Even still, the United States has had historic flashpoints during which states have used their national guards to repress protests or to resist desegregation.94 President Trump's deployment of active-duty troops to Washington, D.C., in June 2020 to contain protests against police brutality and systemic racism prompted one analyst to write: “Such action weakens the fundamental contract between the military and the American people.”95

The theoretical argument presented here focuses on military decision-making rather than military behavior. The argument does not predict which norms may be violated in a given crisis, only that conflict weakens liberal norms, which increases the likelihood that norm violations will occur. To explore the empirical implications, the analyses that follow look at the pathways by which individual shifts in attitudes occur.

The decision to focus on attitudinal shifts, rather than behavioral outcomes, has theoretical justification. Studying how beliefs and attitudes change is valuable in its own right. We cannot assume that beliefs change just because behavior changes (or vice versa). Robert Jervis noted that while beliefs often drive behavior, “such a correspondence is not automatic.”96 Studying each stage separately allows scholars to assess whether and how changes in attitudes affect behavior.97 This separation is particularly important when dealing with complex social processes such as military behavior in domestic crises. This separation also has precedent in the psychology literature, which tends to study either attitude changes as the dependent variable or the effects of attitudes on behavior as independent or intervening variables.98

While this article focuses on how norm conflict affects military attitudes toward norms (rather than behavior), a large psychology literature shows that attitudes are strong predictors of intentions, which in turn shape behavior.99 These studies show that when people have competing attitudes, they act according to their strongest attitude.100

These insights allow us to consider the predicted behavioral implications, although direct tests remain an important step for future research. On the one hand, the U.S. policy expectation is that militaries will continue to prioritize liberal norms, which should in turn continue to shape behavior in benign ways. Even if prioritizing human rights means defying civilian orders, we would expect to see fewer abuses and less intervention if the policy expectation is correct that temporarily choosing human rights does not erode the norm of civilian control. On the other hand, if norm conflict reduces support for liberal norms and soldiers prioritize cohesion instead, the potential for norm-violating behavior increases. Cohesion does not automatically predict liberal norm violations, but it does predict that soldiers will do whatever best serves cohesion, whether that means violating one or both liberal norms.

A broad comparative literature picks up the question of behavioral outcomes, investigating what happens when militaries repress revolutions or defect from the regime instead.101 These works examine how the regime, and those in opposition to the regime, can activate different military interests and identities.102 Many studies suggest that the decision to defect hinges on military cohesion and whether militaries think that repression will undermine cohesion.103 In short, this literature explains the paths that behavior can take once cohesion is a dominant factor in military decision-making.

Cases in Tunisia and Egypt tentatively illustrate these divergent behavioral outcomes. In Tunisia, mass protests in 2011 jeopardized Zine El Abidine Ben Ali's grasp on power. Rather than repress the protests, the military withdrew support from the regime, allowing Ben Ali to fall—but the decision to prioritize human rights did not correspond with reduced support for civilian control.104 In short, the behavioral outcomes in this case aligned to U.S. expectations. Egypt's case initially followed a similar trajectory. When protests erupted against Hosni Mubarak in 2011, the chief of staff of the armed forces assured the U.S. military “that the armed forces would defend Egyptian institutions, not individuals, and would not open fire on civilians.”105 Yet after Mubarak's fall and democratic elections in 2012, the military intervened again a year later, seizing power. Under General Abdel Fattah al-Sisi, elected president in 2014, human rights abuses soared, pointing to an erosion of both liberal norms. The argument advanced in this article presents a causal pathway by which liberal norm conflict may have created the conditions that allowed interests to dominate the Egyptian military's decision-making. The Egyptian case is noteworthy because it serves as a behavioral model for other militaries. In an interview with two AFL officers, I asked what they might do if the norms of human rights and civilian control came into conflict. Without pausing, they answered: “Egypt [the Egyptian military in 2011].”106

To explore the seven hypotheses, I designed an experiment embedded in a survey of active-duty AFL personnel across military bases in Liberia. The experiment primes soldiers in the treatment group to think about liberal norm conflict by asking them to consider a scenario in which the president orders the military to put down protests with force. To avoid potentially biased responses, the soldiers were asked to evaluate the commander's response rather than provide their own preferences directly.107

In Liberia, liberal norm conflict might not only occur but also lead to pernicious outcomes. Dysfunctional civil-military relations contributed to fourteen years of civil war that ravaged the country between 1989 and 2003.108 Today, Liberia is a transitional democracy; elections in 2017 marked the first peaceful transfer of power in over seventy years.109 Rule of law has yet to fully mature; as of 2017 (when the survey was conducted), the AFL still lacked a functioning military justice system.110 Although Liberia is a typical case for liberal norm conflict, it is not an easy case for my theory. After the war, the United States rebuilt the AFL.111 The U.S. training program heavily emphasized liberal norms, socializing the Liberian military to respect human rights and civilian authority. The program architects believed that these norms were key to preventing a repeat of the brutal civil war; by trainers' accounts, the message was well received.112 The war had shattered old norms and AFL recruits were eager for change, making Liberia a most-likely case in which liberal norms could take root. Interviews with the AFL leadership further reveal that the United States tried to instill a preference ordering among the norms, teaching the AFL to obey only legal orders.

Liberia is also a valuable case for assessing the effects of U.S. training because of the high level of U.S. involvement, which helps to shed light on causal pathways. Cases with “extreme” values on independent variables are useful for illustrating mechanisms.113 Furthermore, as exposure to postwar U.S. training varied across recruits, who joined the military in eight waves, there is built-in variation in the army-building program, which tapered off partially by design and partially because it ran out of money before completion.114 In the end, roughly one-third of the rebuilt AFL received the full U.S. training sequence, one-third received partial U.S. training, and one-third received no U.S. training. I leverage this variation to explore differences in experimental treatment effects across levels of training.

I partnered with a local firm, Q&A, to administer the survey in December 2017 to 270 AFL respondents.115 A multistage sampling process drew a random sample of respondents from every unit roster on bases across Liberia.116 AFL rosters indicated that it had fewer than 2,000 soldiers, and thus the sample represents around 15 percent of the force. Because of the small sample size, I treat the results that follow as a plausibility probe of the argument. The survey sample is representative of the force, with AFL recruitment group, rank, and gender distributions tracking closely to the population. Ranks in the sample ranged from private to colonel; the median rank of the survey respondents was specialist, and the median age was thirty-seven years old.117

experimental design

I designed the experiment to prime respondents to recognize a conflict between the liberal norms of human rights and civilian control. Respondents who were randomly assigned to the treatment group heard the following scenario:

After a big tariff increase, local business owners go on strike and there are protests in the streets. The Liberian National Police are managing it, but the president wants to send a forceful message and calls on the military to intervene to stop the protests. The military commander refuses to send soldiers into the streets to stop the protests.

Immediately afterward, as part of the treatment condition, respondents selected the statement that was the closest match to their own opinion about the case: “The military should not have intervened, it was an illegal order”; “The military should have intervened, it was a legal order”; or “It does not matter, as long as the military follows the commander's orders and sticks together.”

I worked with AFL leadership to identify and design a treatment scenario that was a salient example of norm conflict (i.e., an illegal order that soldiers should refuse to obey). The AFL's constitutional role is modeled on that of the United States; it similarly restricts military involvement in domestic law enforcement.118 The 1979 rice riots, a civil-military flashpoint in Liberia, also give this scenario historical precedence.119

Respondents who were randomly assigned to the control group did not hear any scenario. Because the treatment condition included a follow-up question that I used to construct a measure of prioritizing cohesion (described below), respondents in the control group received a similarly structured question about an unrelated topic. They were asked to choose the statement closest to their own opinion about AFL participation in international peacekeeping:120 “International peacekeeping should be a primary mission for the AFL”; “It is okay to contribute to international peacekeeping occasionally, but not as a primary mission”; or “It does not matter, as long as the military executes the mission successfully.”121

After hearing the scenario (or control prompt), respondents were asked a series of outcome measure questions. First, I tested respondents' willingness to prioritize human rights. Respondents were asked whether they agreed with the following statement on a scale from 1 (“not at all”) to 4 (“a lot”): “The military should follow an approach that prioritizes the security of the people over the security of the government.”122 Second, I tested respondents' support for democracy and its alternatives, such as military rule, which represents a rejection of liberal civilian authority. These questions used standardized language from Afrobarometer public opinion surveys.123 Respondents were asked whether they would disapprove or approve of the following alternatives: “Only one political party is allowed to stand for election and hold office”; “The army comes in to govern the country”; and “Elections and the House of Representatives are abolished so that the president can decide everything.” For each alternative, respondents expressed disapproval or approval on a scale from 1 (“strongly disapprove”) to 5 (“strongly approve”).

Respondents were then asked to choose the statement closest to their own opinion from three options: “Democracy is preferable to any other kind of government”; “In some circumstances, a nondemocratic government can be preferable”; and “For someone like me, it doesn't matter what kind of government we have.” Because these response options are categorical, the results that follow used a dummy variable that I coded as 1 if the respondent chose the first option and 0 otherwise.

To evaluate whether respondents prioritized cohesion after hearing the scenario, I coded a dummy variable that took a value of 1 if the respondent chose the third response option to the treatment question (“It does not matter, as long as the military follows the commander's orders and sticks together”) or control question (“It does not matter, as long as the military executes the mission successfully”). These options were designed to capture a rough measure of prioritizing cohesion in each case. This measure cannot provide conclusive evidence of causality because the questions were not worded identically. But it offers suggestive evidence for how norm conflict may affect preferences over cohesion. I also used additional tests to further probe the relationship between norm conflict and cohesion.

measuring u.s. training

To evaluate how foreign military training affects soldiers' responses to norm conflict, I leveraged individual-level data on exposure to U.S. training. The U.S. program to rebuild the AFL began in 2006, with recruits entering the new force in eight groups called “batches” from 2006 through 2015.124 The first batch of recruits were, as the instructors called them, the “guinea pigs.”125 In this “proof of concept” class, 105 soldiers entered basic training in July 2006, and 102 graduated five months later.126 The entire batch moved together through eleven weeks of Initial Entry Training, four weeks of Advanced Individual Training, and a four-week Basic Non-commissioned Officer Course (BNOC).127 Eleven candidates with bachelor's degrees entered an additional six-week Officer Candidate School (OCS), forming the fledgling AFL officer corps. The second batch entered basic training in July 2007.

The period of U.S. training ran from 2006 to 2009 and was primarily executed by two firms, DynCorp International and Pacific Architects & Engineers.128 The early training heavily emphasized liberal norms because the program designers believed “that after 14 years of civil war, most Liberians knew how to fire an AK-47 but did not know when or at what.”129 To inculcate liberal norms, DynCorp invited civics trainers, Liberian academics, and other experts to conduct three weeks of intensive training on the laws of war, civilmilitary relations, and human rights that “dwarfed all other training.”130 This three-week curriculum was the first casualty of funding shortfalls,131 but norms training continued alongside technical training from basic training through OCS.132 As the AFL soldiers went through basic training, their U.S. instructors “kept beating it into [their] heads that the military's role was to serve the population,” subject to civilian control.133 This emphasis on liberal norms was “surprising”; there was “a lot of new doctrine being preached.”134

Importantly, exposure to U.S. training varied across the recruitment batches, which allowed me to test for heterogeneous treatment effects. Batches 1–3 received the full U.S. training sequence, the middle batches (4–5) received varying amounts of training,135 and the final three batches received no U.S. training.136 By 2009, all training responsibilities had transitioned to a Liberian lead; DynCorp only observed the training for batch 6.137 Four years later, the AFL managed its own recruitment and basic training for batch 7, followed by the final batch in 2015.

The amount and quality of training that the Liberian-led batches received declined after batch 5, owing to the lack of Liberian resources or capacity to conduct training on their own. Because the Liberians were not prepared to field their own BNOC or OCS classes, the training sequence was truncated and batches 6–8 failed to produce more than a handful of noncommissioned officers and officers. In 2017, a U.S. military training team went to Liberia to help design new OCS and BNOC courses. They found only one working computer on the training base and no sign of prior curricula.138 The emphasis on norms, which had been rooted in the trainers' beliefs about the causes and effects of Liberia's war, also faded as the U.S. instructors cycled out of the training sequence.

For the tests that follow, I operationalized U.S. training by collapsing the “batch” variable into a dummy “training” variable that I coded as 1 if the respondent joined the AFL in batches 1–5 (any U.S. training) and 0 otherwise.139

This section presents results from empirical tests of my argument about the effects of liberal norm conflict on military decision-making, along with alternative arguments about socialization and the mechanisms that connect norm conflict with prioritization of cohesion. First, I conduct difference-in-means tests across the experimental groups. These tests compare average responses across the treatment and control groups, which allows me to evaluate the effects of respondents' hearing the norm conflict scenario. Because my argument and U.S. policy expectations make opposing predictions, the hypothesis tests are two-tailed. Table 1 reports the results.140

Table 1.
Difference in Means for Respondents Assigned to Treatment and Control
VariableControl MeanTreatment MeanDifference(Standard Error)
Prioritize human rights 3.42 3.19 -0.23 (0.13)∗ 
Support army rule 2.42 2.60 0.18 (0.18) 
Support one-party rule 1.73 1.62 -0.11 (0.12) 
Support one-person rule 1.44 1.45 0.01 (0.09) 
Prefer democracy 0.81 0.80 -0.01 (0.05) 
Prioritize cohesion 0.15 0.30 0.15 (0.05)∗∗∗ 
VariableControl MeanTreatment MeanDifference(Standard Error)
Prioritize human rights 3.42 3.19 -0.23 (0.13)∗ 
Support army rule 2.42 2.60 0.18 (0.18) 
Support one-party rule 1.73 1.62 -0.11 (0.12) 
Support one-person rule 1.44 1.45 0.01 (0.09) 
Prefer democracy 0.81 0.80 -0.01 (0.05) 
Prioritize cohesion 0.15 0.30 0.15 (0.05)∗∗∗ 

NOTE: ∗∗∗ p < 0.01, ∗∗ p < 0.05, ∗ p < 0.01.

The results show that respondents who were exposed to norm conflict—the treatment—are less likely to support prioritizing human rights. The scenario about the government ordering the army to repress protests corresponds with a nearly 0.25 unit decrease in a four-point scale for prioritizing human rights. This finding is consistent with H1, which predicts that moments of norm conflict will reduce soldiers' willingness to prioritize human rights over civilian control. This finding contradicts the U.S. policy expectation laid out in H4, which is that soldiers ought to be more willing to prioritize human rights. Figure 2 graphs the distribution of support for prioritizing human rights across experimental conditions.141

Distribution of Support for Prioritizing Human Rights

Figure 2.
Distribution of Support for Prioritizing Human Rights
Figure 2.
Distribution of Support for Prioritizing Human Rights
Close modal

The results in table 1 also suggest that exposure to norm conflict drives soldiers to prioritize cohesion. The likelihood that respondents prioritize cohesion doubles from no norm conflict (control) to norm conflict (treatment). This finding provides additional support for my argument, consistent with H3, which predicts that moments of norm conflict will lead soldiers to prioritize cohesion. Because of how this measure is constructed, however, these results must be interpreted with caution. Additional tests, described below, provide further evidence that a connection between liberal norm conflict and prioritization of cohesion exists.

The other variables, which measure support for democratic norms, are not significantly different across treatment and control groups. I argue that norm conflict will weaken support for democratic norms (H2), while U.S. policy expectations predict that conflict will sharpen support for them (H5). The signs of the baseline results are generally in the expected direction—respondents exposed to norm conflict are slightly more likely to support army rule and one-person rule, and slightly less likely to always prefer democracy—but none of these effects are statistically significant. In short, the results do not clearly support either hypothesis.

One interpretation of these null results is that while moments of norm conflict produce immediate decisions over which norms to prioritize, norm support erodes more slowly over time.142 Another possibility is that subsequent acts of norm violation weaken norm support, as soldiers attempt to minimize cognitive dissonance caused by divergence between beliefs and behavior. If prioritizing cohesion leads soldiers to defy civilian orders, for example, then we might expect to see a sharper drop in support for democratic norms. Because the survey only measures shifts in support for norms in the immediate moment of norm conflict, assessing the effects of subsequent behavior on attitudes remains an important question for future investigation.

Overall, these initial results provide mixed support for my argument. These baseline results suggest that norm conflict reduces soldiers' willingness to prioritize human rights and increases their inclination to prioritize cohesion, although the effects on support for democratic norms are muted. Importantly, these shifts in support for norms undercut two common policy assumptions. First, liberal training policy hinges on the expectation that soldiers will prioritize human rights when faced with norm conflict; if anything, the opposite is true. Second, liberal policy ignores the possibility that soldiers will prioritize cohesion, but the results suggest that soldiers may choose this norm instead— creating the conditions under which liberal norm violations can occur. These initial comparisons, however, mask the variation across subgroups that I explore next.

conditional effects of training

To examine how U.S. training affects responses to norm conflict, I compare differences in means across treatment and control groups conditioned on level of prior training. I use the “training” dummy variable that takes a value of 1 if the respondent was in an AFL recruitment group that had U.S. training, and 0 otherwise. Figure 3 presents the results.

Effects of Norm Conflict, Conditioned on Level of Training

Figure 3.
Effects of Norm Conflict, Conditioned on Level of Training

NOTE: The figure graphs the contrasts between treatment and control groups for soldiers with and without U.S. training. Results shown with 95 percent confidence intervals.

Figure 3.
Effects of Norm Conflict, Conditioned on Level of Training

NOTE: The figure graphs the contrasts between treatment and control groups for soldiers with and without U.S. training. Results shown with 95 percent confidence intervals.

Close modal

Overall, respondents with U.S. training were significantly less likely to express willingness to prioritize human rights after hearing the norm conflict scenario. They were somewhat less likely to express absolute support for democracy and somewhat more likely to express support for army rule, although these results are not statistically distinguishable from zero. In contrast, respondents without U.S. training were significantly less likely to express support for one-party rule and somewhat less likely to support one-person rule.143 Finally, U.S.-trained respondents were significantly more likely to emphasize cohesion when exposed to norm conflict. Even though not all of the differences are statistically significant, the pattern of coefficients is consistent across measures and provides support for H6a, which predicts that U.S. training will make respondents less willing to prioritize liberal norms.

It is possible that these results are an artifact of small sample size because there were only forty-nine respondents in the “no U.S. training” category.144 More likely, however, is that these results reflect growing identification with the military institution associated with training and time in service. I hypothesize that people who have been in the military longer, receiving more training and socialization, perceive a higher need to protect the organization and become more likely to prioritize cohesion. If this is the case, then, the apparent willingness to prioritize human rights among the least-trained soldiers might reflect less loyalty to the military institution—a quality that would, paradoxically, make them worse soldiers. It is also worth considering that militaries are hierarchical institutions: leaders give orders and the rank and file obey. In the Liberian case, respondents with more U.S. training are also more likely to have command roles. In a crisis, these respondents would be the decision-makers issuing orders. Their unwillingness to prioritize human rights or support liberal norms when exposed to the norm conflict scenario has troubling implications for behavioral outcomes in a real-world crisis.

effects of training without norm conflict

Next, I conduct tests to probe the mechanisms and rule out alternative explanations, including that socialization never happened and that time in service alone explains attitudes toward norms. First, respondents in the survey sample with the most U.S. training are also the soldiers with the most time in service; in other words, U.S. training is collinear to tenure in the military. Rather than U.S. training conditioning the effects of norm conflict, it is possible that tenure in the military conditions attitudes toward norms. If that is the case, then the findings may reflect the failure of training to impart norms in the first place, in line with prevailing arguments about the causes of norm violations among U.S.-trained forces.145

To test this alternative explanation, I evaluate the relationship between U.S. training and support for liberal norms in the absence of norm conflict. I limited the survey sample to respondents who were randomly assigned to the control group and did not hear the treatment scenario (n = 144). I then estimated models that regress the outcome measures on U.S. training, using the “batch” variable that ranges from batch 1 to batch 8. For ease of interpreting the results, I flipped the values of the variable so that higher values indicate earlier batches that received more training.

Each model includes three control variables. The first variable, “education,” is included because it could affect both support for liberal norms and exposure to training. For example, soldiers must meet certain English language proficiency standards to qualify for training in the United States. Education also determines eligibility for the officer corps, in which soldiers receive additional training. The second variable, “wealth,” is an index variable of personal assets commonly used to proxy for wealth.146 As with education, wealth could affect attitudes toward norms as well as the types of education and access to employment opportunities. The third variable is “rank,” a dummy variable that takes a value of 1 if the respondent is in the officer corps. Officers receive different training opportunities and often come from different social backgrounds than the rank and file, which could similarly affect attitudes.

Table 2 presents the results of ordinary least squares regressions; for the democracy model, because of the binary outcome measure, I use a linear probability model with robust standard errors.147 The results show that soldiers with more U.S. training were significantly more likely to express support for liberal norms than soldiers with less U.S. training. Soldiers who received full training (batch 1) were much more likely to express willingness to prioritize human rights over regime security than those who received no training (batch 8). Yet these are the same soldiers who expressed less support for norms in the presence of norm conflict. These results lend support for rejecting two alternative explanations: that socialization never happened in the first place, and that tenure in the military alone shapes attitudes toward norms (at least not in ways that are inherently antithetical to liberal norms).

Table 2.
Training and Support for Liberal Norms
Dependent variable
Human rightsArmy ruleOne-party ruleOne-person ruleDemocracy
Training 0.078∗ (0.046) −0.155∗∗ (0.068) −0.110∗∗ (0.047) −0.106∗∗∗ (0.033) 0.050∗∗∗ (0.018) 
Education −0.036 (0.075) −0.100 (0.110) 0.025 (0.076) 0.075 (0.053) −0.018∗∗∗ (0.028) 
Wealth 0.097 (0.101) −0.165 (0.147) 0.085 (0.102) 0.007 (0.072) 0.039 (0.045) 
Rank −0.215 (0.378) 0.172 (0.549) −0.472 (0.382) − 0.484∗ (0.268) −0.274 (0.181) 
Observations 144 139 140 140 144 
Dependent variable
Human rightsArmy ruleOne-party ruleOne-person ruleDemocracy
Training 0.078∗ (0.046) −0.155∗∗ (0.068) −0.110∗∗ (0.047) −0.106∗∗∗ (0.033) 0.050∗∗∗ (0.018) 
Education −0.036 (0.075) −0.100 (0.110) 0.025 (0.076) 0.075 (0.053) −0.018∗∗∗ (0.028) 
Wealth 0.097 (0.101) −0.165 (0.147) 0.085 (0.102) 0.007 (0.072) 0.039 (0.045) 
Rank −0.215 (0.378) 0.172 (0.549) −0.472 (0.382) − 0.484∗ (0.268) −0.274 (0.181) 
Observations 144 139 140 140 144 

NOTE: Columns 1–4 are ordinary least squares regressions; column 5 is a linear probability model with robust standard errors. ∗∗∗ p < 0.01, ∗∗ p < 0.05, ∗ p < 0.01.

One issue that complicates the ability to interpret these results is that assignments to U.S. training were not random.148 Consequently, age or time effects could also explain variation in attitudes across batches. For example, respon-dents who joined in batch 1 would have been closer to the war chronologically and thus more affected by it. Age could have a similar effect, with older respondents' preferences shaped by longer exposure to conflict. Two factors help to mitigate these concerns. First, because of the timeline of the U.S. program, batches 1–6 were recruited and trained within a narrow window (2006–2009). The largest gap between recruitment and training was between batch 6 and batch 7 (2009–2013). Second, the ages of AFL soldiers are relatively homogenous. Although 60 percent of Liberians are less than twenty-five years old, the median AFL soldier is thirty-seven years old. The AFL has struggled to recruit younger people who can meet its literacy requirements, given the mass disruption of education during the war.149 As a result, 87 percent of the survey sample was over the age of thirty, reducing concerns over age effects.150

Another potential inferential issue is that people who joined in earlier batches may have already left the military, leaving behind those most committed to military service. This selection bias is unlikely for two reasons. First, the AFL lacks formal processes for separating from the force; soldiers' initial contracts were automatically renewed, which kept people in who otherwise might have left.151 Second, the distribution of batches across the survey sample tracks closely to the initial distribution of batches at the force level based on batch graduation figures, which suggests that attrition did not disproportionately affect earlier batches.152

Finally, I consider other alternative arguments. In particular, it could be that U.S. training emphasized civilian control, command and control, or cohesion over human rights, which would explain the decreased support for prioritizing human rights among earlier cohorts. Although the survey experiment does not allow for testing these alternatives directly, qualitative evidence suggests that U.S. training did not emphasize other norms over human rights.

The training program designers regarded the two liberal norms of civilian control and respect for human rights to be mutually reinforcing, but in practice they emphasized human rights because they perceived it as the greater problem in the aftermath of war.153 Interviews with AFL officers likewise revealed an independently minded military that was not unduly subordinate to civilian control. Liberian officers expressed some contempt for what they viewed to be inappropriate political efforts to control the military. As one officer put it, civilians “need to go to school” to get a full understanding of what civilian control means.154 “They don't want the AFL to be too powerful,” he said, “but we control the weapons.” The trainers also did not emphasize blind obedience or command and control in the training. In the words of one of the drill instructors, “If jumping off that cliff was going to kill you, but somebody gave you an order to jump off that cliff, what are you going to do?”155

Interviews with program designers and trainers did not reveal an emphasis on cohesion over liberal norms. The program designers assumed that cohesion would develop organically if they recruited from an ethnically diverse cross section of the population. Their main strategy for fostering cohesion was to conduct statewide recruitment to ensure a representative force.156 For their part, the U.S. military trainers did not teach cohesion in the same way as liberal norms. Instead, they fostered teamwork and solidarity, and they emphasized that a shared military identity should take priority over ethnic or tribal identities.157 In the aftermath of a civil war fought along tribal lines, cohesion was initially weak in the nascent AFL. Together, the U.S. approach and Liberia's history of civil war help explain why AFL soldiers would be motivated to prioritize cohesion under pressure despite intensive liberal norms training.

norm conflict and cohesion

Finally, I conduct two additional tests to explore the relationship between norm conflict and prioritization of cohesion. While each test individually represents a plausibility probe of the argument, their cumulative effect helps to increase confidence in the overall findings.

First, I examine the conditional effects of treatment, given soldiers' prior perceptions of unit-level cohesion. Before exposure to treatment, all respondents were asked a series of questions to probe their perceptions of cohesion and belonging in their units. Drawing on the military sociology literature on cohesion,158 respondents were asked whether they agreed with three statements: “Everyone in this unit works together to achieve our missions”; “If this unit were in combat, any soldier would be willing to risk his life to help another”; and “Soldiers in this unit treat each other equally regardless of their tribe or religion.” The first two statements differentiate between trust in shared competencies and common goals (task cohesion) and interpersonal bonds (social cohesion),159 and the third statement captures perceptions of ethnic divisions or exclusionary practices at the unit level (equality),160 which is also known to affect the quality of cohesion. Answers ranged from 1 (“strongly agree”) to 5 (“strongly disagree”).

Figure 4 displays the conditional treatment effects of unit-level cohesion.161 The solid lines graph the effects of assignment to treatment or control conditioned on prior perceptions of cohesion; the shaded areas indicate the 95 percent confidence intervals. The results show a striking pattern: Soldiers who perceived weak task or social cohesion in their units (i.e., who strongly disagreed that their units were cohesive) were significantly more likely to select the third response option (“It does not matter, as long as the military follows the commander's orders and sticks together”) when exposed to the norm conflict scenario. This finding suggests that soldiers who are worried about cohesion in the first place are more likely to interpret norm conflicts as posing a threat to cohesion. Surprisingly, however, the effect inverts when the question concerns equality. Soldiers who perceived inequitable treatment in their units were significantly less likely to select the third response option; soldiers who felt excluded at the unit level may become alienated from the military organization and thus less vested in its survival.

Conditional Treatment Effects of Unit-Level Cohesion

Figure 4.
Conditional Treatment Effects of Unit-Level Cohesion

NOTE: The figure graphs the effects of exposure to treatment (norm conflict) conditioned on soldiers' perceptions of unit-level cohesion. The gray shading denotes 95 percent confidence intervals.

Figure 4.
Conditional Treatment Effects of Unit-Level Cohesion

NOTE: The figure graphs the effects of exposure to treatment (norm conflict) conditioned on soldiers' perceptions of unit-level cohesion. The gray shading denotes 95 percent confidence intervals.

Close modal

As a final test, I examine how exposure to the norm conflict scenario shaped respondents' thinking about military priorities. After the outcome measures, all respondents were asked the following open-ended question: “What, if anything, does the AFL motto ‘A force for good’ mean to you?” I coded these open-ended responses to create a dummy variable that takes a value of 1 if the response used key words or phrases that invoked cohesion.162 Respondents in the treatment group were more likely to give answers that highlighted cohesion. Table A13 in the online appendix shows that the difference is significant at p < 0.05. This finding provides further evidence that liberal norm conflict heightens soldiers' prioritization of cohesion.

This article has demonstrated that conflicts can arise between the liberal norms of respect for human rights and civilian control of the military. Liberal powers use military training around the world to inculcate these two norms, yet policymakers have neither confronted the reality of this dilemma nor seriously considered its effects. The implicit U.S. policy expectation is that if norm conflict arises, then well-trained, liberally oriented militaries will prioritize human rights over civilian control. Such a choice should be easy to make and benign in its effect on the norms in question. Using experimental data from the Liberian armed forces, I have presented preliminary evidence that challenges this sanguine perspective. First, in contrast to U.S. policy expectations, norm conflict tends to reduce soldiersy willingness to prioritize human rights. Second, norm conflict seems to increase soldiers' prioritization of cohesion. Third, insomuch as U.S. training shapes responses to norm conflict, it makes these effects stronger. These results shed light on a pathway by which liberal norms lose their influence on decision-making relative to other norms aligned to soldiers' interests (e.g., cohesion), creating opportunities for normviolating behavior.

Using survey experiments solves some inferential problems, such as internal validity, but it also introduces others, such as external validity.163 Random assignment to treatment or control conditions is the main way to address internal validity because it helps to establish that other unobserved variables are not driving results. External validity, on the other hand, concerns the generalizability of results. One key concern about external validity is whether the sample accurately represents the population of interest.164 Although random selection ensures that the sample accurately reflects the AFL population, it is important to note that the AFL is unique in two ways. First, it was rebuilt from scratch, with few members having previous military experience. Second, the timing of norm transmission occurred in tandem with basic training. Foreign military training likely affects individuals differently when they come from intact militaries with stronger preexisting norms, and when norms training occurs after early, formative socialization experiences.165 These factors do not necessarily affect the dynamics of norm conflict, but they could make it harder for norms to stick in the first place, diluting the effects of training.

Questions of external validity point to a limitation of survey experiments, which can only be conducted in one context at a time. The solution to this limitation is replication and extension of the experiment across time and space.166 To establish generalizability, future research should explore how different structural and environmental conditions affect how soldiers respond to norm conflict.167 Although Liberia is characterized by weak rule of law, it nonetheless aspires to keep the military out of domestic law enforcement. Future work could look at the problem of norm conflict in states where the military has an internal security mandate; it is also worth replicating in contexts with strong rule of law.168 Additional research could also examine other factors besides foreign training that affect cohesion, such as comparing the effects of norm conflict in states without civil war legacies, or where regime policies promote or undercut cohesion.

How long do the effects of liberal norm conflict persist? Do norms bounce back after the crisis passes, or does norm conflict contribute to permanent erosion of these liberal norms? Connecting attitudinal shifts to behavioral outcomes is an important next step for research. The evidence presented here sheds light on the micro-level dynamics that explain shifts in military support for norms; this experimental work can complement and inform other approaches that link attitudes to behavior.

When the United States, like other liberal powers, builds military capacity in weak states, it uses training to promote liberal norms to solve the dilemma of how to increase capacity while maintaining civilian control and protecting human rights. The policy implication of my findings is that training militaries might encourage norm-violating behavior. This does not mean that U.S. training is worse than other training—military training may generally increase soldiers' prioritization of cohesion under pressure and drive norm violations via other mechanisms.169 But these findings do suggest that U.S. training can backfire in ways that are unique to liberal security assistance; they also suggest that the United States puts false confidence in the power of norms to restrain the militaries that it trains. More training is not the solution. Instead, liberal providers should emphasize building institutions that help to regulate military behavior rather than prioritizing individual or unit-level training with a normative component tacked on.

Liberal providers could also do more to clarify norm hierarchies. By promulgating clear guidelines for behavior and blueprints for decision-making (e.g., “people first, governments second”), some of the problems associated with norm conflict may be mitigated. But doing so requires two policy changes. First, policymakers must admit that this rank-ordering exists. Second, they must modify training curricula to address this hierarchy of norms. The United States might not always want foreign militaries to side with the population, particularly if it means defying a friendly regime. This is an inescapable tradeoff.

Finally, it is worth considering whether the problem of liberal norm conflict gives some providers an advantage over others when it comes to shaping military behavior. China, for example, is a major training provider in Africa. China does not emphasize human rights in its training; instead, it puts a strong and singular value on the norm of civilian (party) control.170 Future research should explore whether there is an “authoritarian advantage” when it comes to foreign military training. The United States prides itself on promoting values in and through security cooperation, a feature that it views as a comparative global strength. Protecting those values means acknowledging their limits and dilemmas.

The author is grateful to Brian Blankenship, Risa Brooks, Jonathan Caverley, Michael Desch, Virginia Page Fortna, Robert Jervis, Richard McAlexander, Barry Posen, Robert Ralston, Laura Resnick Samotin, Jack Snyder, Monica Duffy Toft, and the anonymous reviewers for helpful comments. She also thanks participants in seminars at Columbia University, Yale University, George Washington University, University of Notre Dame, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Ohio State University, and Cato Institute, as well as participants at the 2018 American Political Science Association and 2019 International Studies Association conferences. An online appendix is available at https://doi.org/10.7910/DVN/OA2MTX.

1.

Carey Winfrey, “After Liberia's Costly Rioting, Great Soul-Searching,” New York Times, May 30, 1979, https://www.nytimes.com/1979/05/30/archives/after-liberias-costly-rioting-great-soulsearching-personally.html.

2.

Advocates for Human Rights, A House with Two Rooms: Final Report of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission of Liberia Diaspora Report (Saint Paul, Minn.: DRI Press, 2009), pp. 83–85; and William O'Neill, “Liberia: An Avoidable Tragedy,” Current History, Vol. 92, No. 574 (1993), p. 213, https://www.jstor.org/stable/45316856.

3.

For background on the U.S. military mission to Liberia, see U.S. Agency for International Development, Evaluation of the Public Safety Program for the Republic of Liberia (Washington, D.C.: Department of State, 1972), p. 100.

4.

This definition of norms follows Martha Finnemore and Kathryn Sikkink, “International Norm Dynamics and Political Change,” International Organization, Vol. 52, No. 4 (1998), p. 891, https://doi.org/10.1162/002081898550789. I use “norm” and “idea” interchangeably following Amitav Acharya, “How Ideas Spread: Whose Norms Matter? Norm Localization and Institutional Change in Asian Regionalism,” International Organization, Vol. 58, No. 2 (2004), pp. 239–275, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020818304582024.

5.

For a discussion of human rights and civilian control of the military, see Defense Security Cooperation University [DSCU], Security Cooperation Management, ed. 41 (Arlington, Va.: DSCU, May 2021), pp. 16-1–16-15, https://www.dscu.mil/documents/publications/greenbook/24_Greenbook_41_0_Complete.pdf?id=1.

6.

On repertoires of statecraft, see Stacie E. Goddard, Paul K. MacDonald, and Daniel H. Nexon, “epertoires of Statecraft: Instruments and Logics of Power Politics,” International Relations, Vol. 33, No. 2 (2019), pp. 304–321, https://doi.org/10.1177/0047117819834625.

7.

In contrast, Canada trained around 1,500 personnel from fty-six states that year. Directorate of Military Training and Cooperation, Annual Report/Directorate of Military Training and Cooperation (Ottawa: Canadian Department of National Defence, 2016), http://publications.gc.ca/site/eng/9.850576/publication.html. U.S. data are from the Department of Defense and Department of State, Foreign Military Training and DoD Engagement Activities of Interest, 2019–2020, Vol. 1, Sec. 3 (Washington, D.C.: Bureau of Political-Military Affairs, 2019), https://www.state.gov/reports/foreign-military-training-and-dod-engagement-activities-of-interest-2019-2020/. The annual Foreign Military Training Reports (FMTRs) exclude training conducted with NATO allies, Australia, New Zealand, and Japan.

8.

This calculation is based on my coding of foreign policy objectives in the FMTRs.

9.

Efforts to reform and liberalize military partners grew out of debates over international human rights compliance in the 1970s. See Eric Rittinger, “Arming the Other: American Small Wars, Local Proxies, and the Social Construction of the Principal-Agent Problem,” International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 61, No. 2 (June 2017), pp. 396–409, https://doi.org/10.1093/isq/sqx021. On the use of security assistance to build democratic defense institutions after the end of the Cold War, see Alexandra Gheciu, “Security Institutions as Agents of Socialization? NATO and the ‘New Europe,’“ International Organization, Vol. 59, No. 4 (2005), pp. 973–1012, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020818305050332; and Thomas Bruneau and Harold Trinkunas, “Democratization as a Global Phenomenon and Its Impact on Civil-Military Relations,” Democratization, Vol. 13, No. 5 (2006), pp. 776–790, https://doi.org/10.1080/13500340601010669.

10.

This follows the logic of “socialization as hegemonic power” outlined in G. John Ikenberry and Charles A. Kupchan, “Socialization and Hegemonic Power,” International Organization, Vol. 44, No. 3 (1990), pp. 283–315, https://doi.org/10.1017/S002081830003530X. Because states typically enter into training arrangements voluntarily, providers hope that institutional change in the target military will be cheaper and more effective than efforts to change regimes by force. On the latter, see Alexander B. Downes and Jonathan Monten, “Forced to Be Free? Why Foreign-Imposed Regime Change Rarely Leads to Democratization,” International Security, Vol. 37, No. 4 (Spring 2013), pp. 90–131, https://doi.org/10.1162/ISEC_a_00117.

11.

The U.S. military, for example, fears that human rights abuses perpetrated by its proxies can create backlash for U.S. interests. See U.S. Government Accountability Office [GAO], Security Assistance: U.S. Agencies Should Improve Oversight of Human Rights Training for Foreign Security Forces, GAO-19-554 (Washington, D.C.: GAO, August 2019), p. 2, https://www.gao.gov/products/gao-19-554. Similarly, coup-prone militaries may contribute to political instability, raising the specter of costly military intervention.

12.

On security assistance and coup propensity, see Jesse Dillon Savage and Jonathan D. Caverley, “When Human Capital Threatens the Capitol: Foreign Aid in the Form of Military Training and Coups,” Journal of Peace Research, Vol. 54, No. 4 (2017), pp. 542–557, https://doi.org/10.1177/0022343317713557; and Talukder Maniruzzaman, “Arms Transfers, Military Coups, and Military Rule in Developing States,” Journal of Conflict Resolution, Vol. 36, No. 4 (1992), pp. 733–755, https://doi.org/10.1177/0022002792036004006. On human rights abuses, see Wayne Sandholtz, “United States Military Assistance and Human Rights,” Human Rights Quarterly, Vol. 38, No. 4 (2016), pp. 1070–1101, https://doi.org/10.1353/hrq.2016.0057; and Patricia L. Sullivan, Leo J. Blanken, and Ian C. Rice, “Arming the Peace: Foreign Security Assistance and Human Rights Conditions in Post-Conflict Countries,” Defence and Peace Economics, Vol. 31, No. 2 (2020), pp. 177–200, https://doi.org/10.1080/10242694.2018.1558388.

13.

Simon J. Powelson, “Enduring Engagement Yes, Episodic Engagement No: Lessons for SOF from Mali,” Master's thesis, Naval Postgraduate School, 2013, http://hdl.handle.net/10945/38996; and Tomislav Z. Ruby and Douglas Gibler, “U.S. Professional Military Education and Democratization Abroad,” European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 16, No. 3 (2010), pp. 339–364, https://doi.org/10.1177/1354066109344659.

14.

Stephen Biddle, “Building Security Forces and Stabilizing Nations: The Problem of Agency,” Daedalus, Vol. 146, No. 4 (Fall 2017), pp. 126–138, https://doi.org/10.1162/DAED_a_00464; Daniel L. Byman, “Friends Like These: Counterinsurgency and the War on Terrorism,” International Security, Vol. 31, No. 2 (Fall 2006), pp. 79–115, https://doi.org/10.1162/isec.2006.31.2.79; and Walter C. Ladwig III, “Influencing Clients in Counterinsurgency: U.S. Involvement in El Salvador's Civil War, 1979–92,” International Security, Vol. 41, No. 1 (Summer 2016), pp. 99–146, https://doi.org/10.1162/ISEC_a_00250.

15.

See DSCU, Security Cooperation Management, p. 16–1.

16.

Jonathan Baron and Mark Spranca, “Protected Values,” Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, Vol. 70, No. 1 (1997), pp. 1–16, https://doi.org/10.1006/obhd.1997.2690; and Philip E. Tetlock, “Thinking the Unthinkable: Sacred Values and Taboo Cognitions,” Trends in Cognitive Sciences, Vol. 7, No. 7 (2003), pp. 320–324, https://doi.org/10.1016/S1364-6613(03)00135-9.

17.

Antje Wiener, A Theory of Contestation (Heidelberg: Springer, 2014); Antje Wiener, Contestation and Constitution of Norms in Global International Relations (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2018); and Acharya, “How Ideas Spread.”

18.

Thomas M. Dolan, “Unthinkable and Tragic: The Psychology of Weapons Taboos in War,” International Organization, Vol. 67, No. 1 (2013), pp. 37–63, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020818312000379; and Vaughn P. Shannon, “Norms Are What States Make of Them: The Political Psychology of Norm Violation,” International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 44, No. 2 (2000), pp. 293–316, https://doi.org/10.1111/0020-8833.00159.

19.

Dolan, “Unthinkable and Tragic,” p. 48; Tetlock, “Thinking the Unthinkable,” p. 324; and Jonathan Baron and Sarah Leshner, “How Serious Are Expressions of Protected Values?” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied, Vol. 6, No. 3 (2000), pp. 183–194, https://doi.org/10.1037/1076-898X.6.3.183.

20.

For a similar approach to studying military decision-making, see Eric Hundman and Sarah E. Parkinson, “Rogues, Degenerates, and Heroes: Disobedience as Politics in Military Organizations,” European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 25, No. 3 (2019), pp. 645–671, https://doi.org/10.1177/1354066118823891.

21.

Diana Panke and Ulrich Petersohn, “Why International Norms Disappear Sometimes,” European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 18, No. 4 (2012), pp. 719–742, https://doi.org/10.1177/1354066111407690.

22.

Cohesion is a group-oriented norm, whereas liberal norms tend to be individually held beliefs. The dynamics explored here suggest that norm conflict could activate tension between individual and group norms, which is an important question for future research.

23.

Scott D. Sagan, Benjamin A. Valentino, Charli Carpenter, and Alexander H. Montgomery, “Does the Noncombatant Immunity Norm Have Stopping Power? A Debate,” International Security, Vol. 45, No. 2 (Fall 2020), pp. 174–175, https://doi.org/10.1162/isec_a_00393.

24.

In this article, I use “democratic norms” as a substitute for liberal conceptions of democracy and civilian control of the military.

25.

Risa Brooks, “Paradoxes of Professionalism: Rethinking Civil-Military Relations in the United States,” International Security, Vol. 44, No. 4 (Spring 2020), pp. 7–44, https://doi.org/10.1162/isec_a_00374.

26.

Shannon, “Norms Are What States Make of Them”; and Sonia Cardenas, “Norm Collision: Explaining the Effects of International Human Rights Pressure on State Behavior,” International Studies Review, Vol. 6, No. 2 (June 2004), pp. 213–232, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1521-9488.2004.00396.x.

27.

Bruneau and Trinkunas, “Democratization as a Global Phenomenon.” Although this article focuses on liberal norms, illiberal providers also use security assistance to impart norms. For example, China cites foreign assistance training as one way that it promotes human rights, which it defines as “the rights to subsistence and development.” State Council Information Office of the People's Republic of China, Progress in Human Rights Over the 40 Years of Reform and Opening Up in China (Beijing: Foreign Languages Press, 2018), http://english.www.gov.cn/archive/white_paper/2018/12/13/content_281476431737638.htm.

28.

Ministry of Defence, Building Stability Overseas Strategy (London: Ministry of Defence, Department for International Development, Foreign and Commonwealth Office, 2011), p. 12, https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/building-stability-overseas-strategy.

29.

Directorate of Military Training and Cooperation, Annual Report.

30.

The White House, “Fact Sheet: U.S. Security Sector Assistance Policy,” April 5, 2013, https://www.hsdl.org/?view&did=747214.

31.

Foreign Security Forces: Authority to Build Capacity, 10 U.S.C. § 333 (2016) https://www.law.cornell.edu/uscode/text/10/333.

32.

This estimate counts only states where the FMTR foreign policy objectives include norms, not states that receive training for other objectives that have a normative component tacked on to satisfy a legal requirement.

33.

In regions where the United States has more strategic interests, such as the Middle East and Asia, it tends to emphasize more oblique norms of “professionalism.”

34.

See Theo Farrell, “World Culture and Military Power,” Security Studies, Vol. 14, No. 3 (2005), pp. 448–488, https://doi.org/10.1080/09636410500323187; Robert M. Price, “A Theoretical Approach to Military Rule in New States: Reference-Group Theory and the Ghanaian Case,” World Politics, Vol. 23, No. 3 (1971), pp. 399–430, https://doi.org/10.2307/2009620; and Ruby and Gibler, “U.S. Professional Military Education and Democratization Abroad.”

35.

Gheciu, “Security Institutions as Agents of Socialization?”; Jeffrey T. Checkel, “Socialization and Violence,” Journal of Peace Research, Vol. 54, No. 5 (2017), pp. 592–605, https://doi.org/10.1177/0022343317721813; Amelia Hoover Green, The Commander's Dilemma: Violence and Restraint in Wartime (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 2018); Alastair Iain Johnston, “Treating International Institutions as Social Environments,” International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 45, No. 4 (2001), pp. 487505, https://doi.org/10.1111/0020-8833.00212; and James G. March and Johan P. Olsen, Rediscovering Institutions: The Organizational Basis of Politics (New York: Free Press, 1989), p. 30.

36.

Finnemore and Sikkink, “International Norm Dynamics and Political Change,” p. 905.

37.

Ibid., p. 899.

38.

Author interview via Zoom with former DynCorp instructor D, June 12, 2021.

39.

Carla Martinez Machain, “Exporting Influence: U.S. Military Training as Soft Power,” Journal of Conflict Resolution, Vol. 65, No. 2/3 (2021), pp. 313–341, https://doi.org/10.1177/0022002720957713.

40.

DSCU, Security Cooperation Management, p. 16–1. The Defense Department conducts norms training around the world. For example, the Defense Institute of International Legal Studies conducts over 100 events globally each year on “human rights, international humanitarian law, and the law of armed conflicts.” See Defense Institute of International Legal Studies, “About Us,” https://globalnetplatform.org/diils/about-diils/.

41.

Author interview via telephone with Defense Department official, November 30, 2018.

42.

Author interview via telephone with Michigan National Guard adviser, October 13, 2014.

43.

Terence Lee, “Military Cohesion and Regime Maintenance: Explaining the Role of the Military in 1989 China and 1998 Indonesia,” Armed Forces and Society, Vol. 32, No. 1 (2005), p. 84, https://doi.org/10.1177/0095327X05277906; and Defense Management Study Group on Military Cohesion, Cohesion in the U.S. Military (Washington, D.C.: National Defense University Press, 1984), ix. Cohesion has affective and instrumental dimensions, encompassing how military members feel about each other as well as their commitment to shared goals. Some scholars distinguish between these dimensions, calling the former “social cohesion” and the latter “task cohesion.” See Guy L. Siebold, “The Essence of Military Group Cohesion,” Armed Forces and Society, Vol. 33, No. 2 (2007), pp. 286–295, https://doi.org/10.1177/0095327X06294173; and Anthony King, “The Existence of Group Cohesion in the Armed Forces: A Response to Guy Siebold,” Armed Forces and Society, Vol. 33, No. 4 (2007), pp. 638–645, https://doi.org/10.1177/0095327X07301445.

44.

Cohesion is “mutually beneficial” to group members because it increases the likelihood of mission success and survival in combat situations. See Guy L. Siebold, “Key Questions and Challenges to the Standard Model of Military Group Cohesion,” Armed Forces and Society, Vol. 37, No. 3 (2011), p. 459, https://doi.org/10.1177/0095327X11398450; and Robert J. MacCoun, Elizabeth Kier, and Aaron Belkin, “Does Social Cohesion Determine Motivation in Combat? An Old Question with an Old Answer,” Armed Forces and Society, Vol. 32, No. 4 (2006), p. 652, https://doi.org/10.1177/0095327X05279181.

45.

Eva Bellin, “Reconsidering the Robustness of Authoritarianism in the Middle East: Lessons from the Arab Spring,” Comparative Politics, Vol. 44, No. 2 (2012), p. 131, https://doi.org/10.5029/001041502798838021; and Barbara Geddes, “What Do We Know About Democratization after Twenty Years?,” Annual Review of Political Science, Vol. 2, No. 1 (1999), p. 126, https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.polisci.2.1.115.

46.

David Pion-Berlin, Diego Esparza, and Kevin Grisham, “Staying Quartered: Civilian Uprisings and Military Disobedience in the Twenty-First Century,” Comparative Political Studies, Vol. 47, No. 2 (2014), p. 247, https://doi.org/10.1177/0010414012450566.

47.

The social psychology and military sociology literatures often treat cohesion as a process of integration or a pattern of bonding. See, for example, Noah E. Friedkin, “Social Cohesion,” Annual Review of Sociology, Vol. 30, No. 1 (2004), pp. 409–425, https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.soc.30.012703.110625. Treatment of cohesion as a norm or interest is more common in the political science literature.

48.

Societal and political factors include ethnic identities, regime policies, and historical legacies. See, for example, Jasen J. Castillo, Endurance and War: The National Sources of Military Cohesion (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 2014); Theodore McLauchlin, “Loyalty Strategies and Military Defection in Rebellion,” Comparative Politics, Vol. 42, No. 3 (2010), pp. 333–350, https://doi.org/10.5029/001041500X12911363509792; and Alex Neads, “You're in the Army Now: The Politics of Cohesion During Military Integration in Sierra Leone,” Security Studies, Vol. 29, No. 5 (2020), pp. 894–926, https://doi.org/10.1080/09636412.2020.1859126. On training and operational practices, see Anthony King, “The Word of Command: Communication and Cohesion in the Military,” Armed Forces and Society, Vol. 32, No. 4 (2006), pp. 493–502, https://doi.org/10.1177/0095327X05283041; and Elizabeth Kier, “Homosexuals in the U.S. Military: Open Integration and Combat Effectiveness,” International Security, Vol. 23, No. 2 (Fall 1998), pp. 5–39, https://doi.org/10.1162/isec.23.2.5.

49.

Anthony King, “On Combat Effectiveness in the Infantry Platoon: Beyond the Primary Group Thesis,” Security Studies, Vol. 25, No. 4 (2016), pp. 699–728, https://doi.org/10.1080/09636412.2016.1220205; and Kier, “Homosexuals in the U.S. Military.”

50.

Author interview via Zoom with former DynCorp instructor D, June 12, 2021.

51.

Author interview with AFL officers A and B, Monrovia, July 19, 2017. Basic aspects of soldiering were new to most recruits because of the decision to disband the old AFL and extensively vet new recruits. As a result, relatively few recruits had prior combat experience either as rebels or as government forces.

52.

Author interview with AFL officer C, Monrovia, July 20, 2017.

53.

Savage and Caverley, “When Human Capital Threatens the Capitol”; and Sandholtz, “United States Military Assistance and Human Rights.”

54.

“School of the Dictators,” New York Times, September 28, 1996, https://www.nytimes.com/1996/09/28/opinion/school-of-the-dictators.html.

55.

Powelson, “Enduring Engagement Yes, Episodic Engagement No”; Ruby and Gibler, “U.S. Professional Military Education and Democratization Abroad”; and Carol Atkinson, “Constructivist Implications of Material Power: Military Engagement and the Socialization of States 19722000,” International Studies Quarterly, Vol. 50, No. 3 (2006), pp. 509–537, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-2478.2006.00412.x.

56.

Tyrone C. Marshall Jr., “Africom Commander Addresses Concerns, Potential Solutions in Mali,” American Forces Press Service, January 24, 2013, https://military-veteran.com/newsart/afps/art/649.

57.

For an overview of principal-agent theory, see Jean-Jacques Laffont and David Martimort, The Theory of Incentives: The Principal-Agent Model (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2002); and Gary J. Miller, “The Political Evolution of Principal-Agent Models,” Annual Review of Political Science, Vol. 8, No. 1 (2005), pp. 203–225, https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.polisci.8.082103.104840.

58.

These studies examine why the United States often fails to achieve its goals working with proxies in counterterrorism and counterinsurgency campaigns. See Eli Berman and David A. Lake, eds., Proxy Wars: Suppressing Violence through Local Agents (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 2019); Stephen Biddle, Julia Macdonald, and Ryan Baker, “Small Footprint, Small Payoff: The Military Effectiveness of Security Force Assistance,” Journal of Strategic Studies, Vol. 41, No. 1/2 (2018), pp. 89–142, https://doi.org/10.1080/01402390.2017.1307745; Byman, “Friends Like These”; Barbara Elias, “The Big Problem of Small Allies: New Data and Theory on Defiant Local Counter-insurgency Partners in Afghanistan and Iraq,” Security Studies, Vol. 27, No. 2 (2018), pp. 233–262, https://doi.org/10.1080/09636412.2017.1386935; and Walter C. Ladwig III, The Forgotten Front: Patron-Client Relationships in Counterinsurgency (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2017).

59.

On the need for “both/and” arguments, see Michael Zürn and Jeffrey T. Checkel, “Getting Socialized to Build Bridges: Constructivism and Rationalism, Europe and the Nation-State,” International Organization, Vol. 59, No. 4 (2005), p. 1046, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020818305050356.

60.

Utilitarian norms refer to norms that maximize the military's well-being as opposed to norms that reflect moral rules, such as not abusing human rights.

61.

Samuel A. Stouffer, “An Analysis of Conflicting Social Norms,” American Sociological Review, Vol. 14, No. 5 (December 1949), pp. 707–717, https://doi.org/10.2307/2086672; and Philip E. Tetlock, “Social Functionalist Frameworks for Judgment and Choice: Intuitive Politicians, Theologians, and Prosecutors,” Psychological Review, Vol. 109, No. 3 (2002), pp. 450–471, https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.109.3.450.

62.

Dolan, “Unthinkable and Tragic,” p. 42; Jon Elster, Alchemies of the Mind: Rationality and the Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999); and Tetlock, “Social Functionalist Frameworks for Judgment and Choice.”

63.

Ian Hurd, “Breaking and Making Norms: American Revisionism and Crises of Legitimacy,” International Politics, Vol. 44, No. 2/3 (2007), pp. 194–213, https://doi.org/10.1057/palgrave.ip.8800184; and Martha Finnemore, “Legitimacy, Hypocrisy, and the Social Structure of Unipolarity: Why Being a Unipole Isn't All It's Cracked Up to Be,” World Politics, Vol. 61, No. 1 (2009), pp. 5885, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0043887109000082.

64.

Paul Kowert and Jeffrey Legro, “Norms, Identity and Their Limits: A Theoretical Reprise,” in Peter J. Katzenstein, ed., The Culture of National Security: Norms and Identity in World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), p. 486.

65.

For example, see Friedrich V. Kratochwil, Rules, Norms, and Decisions on the Conditions of Practical and Legal Reasoning in International Relations and Domestic Affairs (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989); Oscar Schachter, International Law in Theory and Practice (Norwell, Mass.: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991); Stouffer, “An Analysis of Conflicting Social Norms”; James G. March and Johan P. Olsen, Ambiguity and Choice in Organizations (Oslo: Universitetsforlaget, 1976); Jeffrey W. Legro, “Which Norms Matter? Revisiting the ‘Failure’ of Internationalism,” International Organization, Vol. 50, No. 1 (1997), pp. 31–63, https://doi.org/10.1162/002081897550294; and Wayne Sandholtz, “Dynamics of International Norm Change: Rules against Wartime Plunder,” European Journal of International Relations, Vol. 14, No. 1 (2008), pp. 101–131, https://doi.org/10.1177/1354066107087766.

66.

Jennifer M. Welsh, “Norm Contestation and the Responsibility to Protect,” Global Responsibility to Protect, Vol. 5, No. 4 (2013), pp. 365–396, https://doi.org/10.1163/1875984X-00504002.

67.

In 1994, for example, the State Department legal counsel advised against jamming Rwandan hate radio broadcasts partly over concerns about U.S. commitment to free speech. Samantha Power, A Problem from Hell: America and the Age of Genocide (New York: Basic Books, 2002).

68.

Jon Elster, The Cement of Society: A Study of Social Order (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989), p. 100.

69.

An exception is Jesse Savage and Jonathan Caverley, who, although skeptical about socialization, note “the tension built within the stated goals of promoting both human rights and civilian supremacy.” Savage and Caverley, “When Human Capital Threatens the Capitol,” p. 544.

70.

DSCU, Security Cooperation Management, p. 16–5.

71.

Eric A. Nordlinger, Soldiers in Politics: Military Coups and Governments (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1977), p. 8.

72.

DSCU, Security Cooperation Management, p. 16–1.

73.

See James B. Insco, “Defense of Superior Orders before Military Commissions,” Duke Journal of Comparative & International Law, Vol. 13, No. 2 (2003), pp. 389–418, https://scholarship.law.duke.edu/djcil/vol13/iss2/4.

74.

Lindsay Cohn, Max Margulies, and Michael A. Robinson, “What Discord Follows: The Divisive Debate over Military Disobedience,” War on the Rocks, August 2, 2019, https://warontherocks.com/2019/08/what-discord-follows-the-divisive-debate-over-military-disobedience/.

75.

U.S. Africa Command, Testimony of Gen. Thomas D. Waldhauser, Commander, United States Africa Command, 115th Congress, 2nd Session (Washington, D.C.: 2018), p. 5, https://www.africom.mil/document/30467/u-s-africa-command-2018-posture-statement.

76.

Author interview with AFL officer C, Monrovia, July 20, 2017; author interviews with U.S. instructors and a review of the civics curriculum confirm that instructors conveyed this rank-ordering in Liberia; author interview via Zoom with former DynCorp instructor A, May 27, 2021; and author interview via Zoom with former DynCorp instructors B and C, June 5, 2021.

77.

Philip E. Tetlock et al., “The Psychology of the Unthinkable: Taboo Trade-Offs, Forbidden Base Rates, and Heretical Counterfactuals,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 78, No. 5 (2000), pp. 853–870, https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3504.78.5.853; Baron and Leshner, “How Serious Are Expressions of Protected Values?”; Philip E. Tetlock, Barbara A. Mellers, and J. Peter Scoblic, “Sacred versus Pseudo-Sacred Values: How People Cope with Taboo Trade-Offs,” American Economic Review, Vol. 107, No. 5 (2017), pp. 96–99, https://doi.org/10.1257/aer.p20171110; and Dolan, “Unthinkable and Tragic.”

78.

This assumption is shared in the psychology literature on value tradeoffs. See Baron and Spranca, “Protected Values,” p. 1; and Dolan, “Unthinkable and Tragic,” p. 47.

79.

Wiener, A Theory of Contestation; and Wiener, Contestation and Constitution of Norms in Global International Relations.

80.

Shannon, “Norms Are What States Make of Them.”

81.

Dolan, “Unthinkable and Tragic”; Charli Carpenter and Alexander H. Montgomery, “The Stopping Power of Norms: Saturation Bombing, Civilian Immunity, and U.S. Attitudes toward the Laws of War,” International Security, Vol. 45, No. 2 (Fall 2020), p. 147, https://doi.org/10.1162/isec_a_00392; Scott D. Sagan and Benjamin A. Valentino, “Revisiting Hiroshima in Iran: What Americans Really Think about Using Nuclear Weapons and Killing Noncombatants,” International Security, Vol. 42, No. 1 (Summer 2017), pp. 41–79; and Sagan, Valentino, Carpenter, and Montgomery, “Does the Noncombatant Immunity Norm Have Stopping Power?”

82.

Hurd, “Breaking and Making Norms,” p. 197.

83.

Incentives to avoid fracturing the ranks explain different military behaviors, including coup attempts. See Geddes, “What Do We Know About Democratization after Twenty Years?”; and Samuel E. Finer, The Man on Horseback: The Role of the Military in Politics (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1988).

84.

See Lee, “Military Cohesion and Regime Maintenance”; Zoltan Barany, How Armies Respond to Revolutions and Why (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2016); Julien Morency-Laflamme, “A Question of Trust: Military Defection during Regime Crises in Benin and Togo,” Democratization, Vol. 25, No. 3 (2018), pp. 464–480, https://doi.org/10.1080/13500347.2017.1375474; and McLauchlin, “Loyalty Strategies and Military Defection in Rebellion.”

85.

Shannon, “Norms Are What States Make of Them”; and for a related argument on norm change, see Aisha Ahmad, “‘We Have Captured Your Women’: Explaining Jihadist Norm Change,” International Security, Vol. 44, No. 1 (Summer 2019), pp. 80–116, https://doi.org/10.1162/isec_a_00350.

86.

On value tradeoffs, see Baron and Spranca, “Protected Values,” p. 1; Robert Jervis, “Understanding Beliefs,” Political Psychology, Vol. 27, No. 5 (2006), pp. 641–663, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9221.2006.00527.x; and Robert Jervis, Perception and Misperception in International Politics (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1976).

87.

Author interview via telephone with Defense Department official, November 30, 2018.

88.

An example of such rhetoric is President Ronald Reagan's position on denying arms to El Salvador over human rights abuses committed in their civil war: “We don't throw out our friends just because they can't pass the ‘saliva test’ on human rights.” President Ronald Reagan, “Minutes of a National Security Council Meeting,” February 6,1981, Foreign Relations of the United States, Vol. III, Doc. 15, Soviet Union, January 1981-January 1983, (Washington, D.C.: Government Printing Office, 2016).

89.

In the analyses that follow, I look at individual-level support as one dimension of norm robustness. Other dimensions beyond the scope of this article include “concordance, third-party reactions to norm violations … and implementation.” See Nicole Deitelhoff and Lisbeth Zimmermann, “Norms under Challenge: Unpacking the Dynamics of Norm Robustness,” Journal of Global Security Studies, Vol. 4, No. 1 (2019), p. 2, https://doi.org/10.1093/jogss/ogy041.

90.

Pseudo-democratic refers to states that have the trappings of democratic institutions without true democracy. Such states are also known as “hybrid regimes.” See Larry Diamond, “Elections Without Democracy: Thinking About Hybrid Regimes,” Journal of Democracy, Vol. 13, No. 2 (2002), pp. 21–35, https://doi.org/10.1353/jod.2002.0025.

91.

Cases of political upheaval in the developing world often feature embattled governments ordering militaries to repress protests, which forces the military to choose sides. Coups occurred in Nigeria in the 1960s, for example, after military commanders had to choose between fighting to “maintain the government in power or overthrowing it themselves.” Nordlinger, Soldiers and Politics, p. 91.

92.

Associated Press, “Equating Rocks with Rifles, Trump Proposes Radical New Rules of Engagement for Troops along Border,” Military Times, November 1, 2018, https://www.militarytimes.com/news/your-military/2018/11/01/equating-rocks-with-rifles-trump-proposes-radical-new-rules-of-engagement-for-troops-along-border/; and Tara Copp, “Here Are the Rules of Engagement for Troops Deploying to the Mexican Border,” Military Times, November 2, 2018, https://www.militarytimes.com/news/your-military/2018/11/02/here-are-the-rules-of-engagement-for-troops-deploying-to-the-mexican-border/.

93.

The military's mission orientation might also affect the degree to which soldiers perceive there to be a norm conflict (e.g., in orders to repress protests), a question for future research.

94.

An example of using the national guard to repress protests includes when members of the Ohio National Guard fired on student protestors at Kent State University on May 4, 1970, killing four and injuring nine. See Jerry M. Lewis and Thomas R. Hensley, “The May 4 Shootings at Kent State University: The Search for Historical Accuracy,” M4Y, Kent State University, https://www.kent.edu/may-4-historical-accuracy; and Jonathon Berlin and Kori Rumore, “12 Times the President Called in the Military Domestically,” Chicago Tribune, June 1, 2020, http://www.chicagotribune.com/news/ct-national-guard-deployments-timeline-htmlstory.html.

95.

Paula Thornhill, “‘Beyond the Beltway’—What's the Civil-Military Crisis?,” War on the Rocks, June 17, 2020, https://warontherocks.com/2020/06/beyond-the-beltway-whats-the-civil-military-crisis/.

96.

Jervis, “Understanding Beliefs,” p. 657.

97.

Jack Levy also calls for two-stage approaches that measure both belief and behavior change. See Jack S. Levy, “Learning and Foreign Policy: Sweeping a Conceptual Minefield,” International Organization, Vol. 48, No. 2 (1994), pp. 279–312, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020818300028198.

98.

Alice H. Eagly, “Uneven Progress: Social Psychology and the Study of Attitudes,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 63, No. 5 (1992), p. 705, https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3504.63.5.693.

99.

The theory of planned behavior argues that attitudes and norms shape intentions, which are the immediate predictors of behavior. See Martin Fishbein and Icek Ajzen, Belief, Attitude, Intention, and Behavior: An Introduction to Theory and Research (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1975); and Icek Ajzen, “The Theory of Planned Behavior,” Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, Vol. 50, No. 2 (1991), pp. 179–211, https://doi.org/10.1016/0749-5978(91)90020-T. The theory of planned behavior has been used to predict a wide range of behaviors, from road rage to vaccination. Other models linking attitudes to behavior include Alice H. Eagly and Shelly Chaiken, The Psychology of Attitudes (Fort Worth, Texas: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1993).

100.

Andrew R. Davidson and Diane M. Morrison, “Predicting Contraceptive Behavior from Attitudes: A Comparison of Within-Versus Across-Subjects Procedures,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 45, No. 5 (1983), pp. 997–1009, https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3504.45.5.997.

101.

Revolutions are an extreme case; my argument does not require revolutionary moments, just a conflict between the imperatives to protect people and to obey political leaders, which could happen during unrest short of widescale rebellion.

102.

See, for example, Aurel Croissant, David Kuehn, and Tanja Eschenauer, “The ‘Dictator's Endgame’: Explaining Military Behavior in Nonviolent Anti-Incumbent Mass Protests,” Democracy and Security, Vol. 14, No. 2 (2018), pp. 174–199, https://doi.org/10.1080/17419166.2017.1423471; Holger Albrecht and Dorothy Ohl, “Exit, Resistance, Loyalty: Military Behavior during Unrest in Authoritarian Regimes,” Perspectives on Politics, Vol. 14, No. 1 (2016), pp. 38–52, https://doi.org/10.1017/S1537592715003217; Bellin, “Reconsidering the Robustness of Authoritarianism in the Middle East”; and Michael Makara, “Coup-Proofing, Military Defection, and the Arab Spring,” Democracy and Security, Vol. 9, No. 4 (2013), pp. 334–359, https://doi.org/10.1080/17419166.2013.802983.

103.

Lee, “Military Cohesion and Regime Maintenance”; Barany, How Armies Respond to Revolutions and Why; Morency-Laflamme, “A Question of Trust”; and McLauchlin, “Loyalty Strategies and Military Defection in Rebellion.” David Pion-Berlin et al. and Eva Bellin suggest that militaries are more likely to disobey orders when they worry that repression will undermine cohesion. Pion-Berlin, Esparza, and Grisham, “Staying Quartered”; and Bellin, “Reconsidering the Robustness of Authoritarianism in the Middle East.” The implication is that cohesive militaries will be more likely to repress civilians, but cohesion could also make units more likely to defy orders. See Jesse Paul Lehrke, “A Cohesion Model to Assess Military Arbitration of Revolutions,” Armed Forces and Society, Vol. 40, No. 1 (2014), pp. 156–157, https://doi.org/10.1177/0095327X12459850.

104.

David Kuehn, “Midwives or Gravediggers of Democracy? The Military's Impact on Democratic Development,” Democratization, Vol. 24, No. 5 (2017), p. 786, https://doi.org/10.1080/13500347.2017.1324421; and Risa Brooks, “Abandoned at the Palace: Why the Tunisian Military Defected from the Ben Ali Regime in January 2011,” Journal of Strategic Studies, Vol. 36, No. 2 (2013), pp. 205–220, https://doi.org/10.1080/01402390.2012.742011.

105.

Scott Shane and David D. Kirkpatrick, “Military Caught between Mubarak and Protesters,” New York Times, February 10, 2011, https://www.nytimes.com/2011/02/11/world/middleeast/11military.html.

106.

Author interview with AFL officers A and B, Monrovia, July 19, 2017.

107.

The alternative would be to ask people directly what they would do in such a situation. But such questions could result in biased estimates if people perceived truthful answers as being socially undesirable. See Theresa DeMaio, “Social Desirability and Survey Measurement: A Review,” in Charles F. Turner and Elizabeth Martin, eds., Surveying Subjective Phenomenon, Vol. 2 (Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Sage, 1984). Another problem is that people may not correctly identify their true preferences. Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, “Rational Choice and the Framing of Decisions,” Journal of Business, Vol. 59, No. 4 (1986), pp. S250-S278, https://doi.org/10.1086/296365; and Amos Tversky and Richard H. Thaler, “Anomalies: Preference Reversals,” Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 4, No. 2 (Spring 1990), pp. 201–211, https://doi.org/10.1257/jep.4.2.201.

108.

For background on the war, as well as historical U.S. security assistance in Liberia, see Josef Teboho Ansorge and Nana Akua Antwi-Ansorge, “Monopoly, Legitimacy, Force: DDR-SSR Liberia,” in Melanne A. Civic and Michael Miklaucic, eds., Monopoly of Force: The Nexus of DDR and SSR (Washington, D.C.: National Defense University Press, 2011).

109.

Reuters Staff, “White House: Liberia Transfer of Power a ‘Major Milestone,’“ Reuters, December 29, 2017, https://www.reuters.com/article/us-liberia-election-usa/white-house-liberia-transfer-of-power-a-major-milestone-idUSKBN1EN1K7.

110.

Author interview with UN Mission in Liberia (UNMIL) officials A and B, Monrovia, July 17, 2017.

111.

The United States and the United Nations (UN) shared post-conflict security sector reform in Liberia, with the United States supporting military reform and UNMIL supporting police and rule-of-law reform. This article focuses on U.S. efforts to rebuild the AFL. On UN efforts, see “Background,” United Nations Mission in Liberia, last modified March 20, 2018, https://unmil.unmissions.org/background.

112.

Author interview via Zoom with former DynCorp instructor A, May 27, 2021; and author interview via Zoom with former DynCorp instructors B and C, June 5, 2021.

113.

Alexander L. George and Andrew Bennett, Case Studies and Theory Development in the Social Sciences (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2005); and Jason Seawright, Multi-Method Social Science: Combining Qualitative and Quantitative Tools (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2016).

114.

The program was funded by a one-time appropriation from Congress. When the money ran out, the program ended. Author interview via telephone with State Department official A, August 21, 2014; and Sean McFate, Building Better Armies: An Insider's Account of Liberia (Carlisle, Pa.: Strategic Studies Institute, U.S. Army War College Press, 2013), p. 30, https://www.jstor.org/stable/resrep11245.

115.

Two factors drove the survey's timing: the 2017 elections, and the March 2018 closure of UNMIL. December 2017 represented a window of opportunity to evaluate the effects of training on the AFL after the main effort had ended but before the political status quo changed.

116.

See the online appendix for additional details.

117.

There were only two general officers in the military as of 2017, both of whom participated in in-depth, semi-structured interviews. Summary statistics are in the online appendix.

118.

According to the 2008 National Defense Act, the AFL may intervene in emergencies “only as a last resort, when the threat exceeds the capacity of law enforcement agencies to respond.” The scenario notes that the police are “managing” the situation, which AFL leaders felt clearly signaled that the order was illegal.

119.

Although the rice riots were important, they occurred thirty-eight years prior to the survey. To the extent that effects persisted, it is unclear in what direction they might affect results. “Pretreatment” through real-world events can lead to underestimating treatment effects. If anything, the events of 1979 might make respondents more attuned to human rights, biasing results in favor of U.S. policy expectations.

120.

International peacekeeping is not controversial in Liberia. It is an AFL mission outlined in the 2008 National Defense Act, although opinions vary over whether it should be a primary or secondary mission.

121.

Figure A3 in the online appendix summarizes the experimental design.

122.

I use the term “security of the people” to capture the concept of human rights because the Liberian and U.S. militaries use similar terms to talk about the military's role in protecting human rights. Author interview with AFL officer C, Monrovia, July 20, 2017; and U.S. Africa Command, Testimony of Gen. Thomas D. Waldhauser, p. 5.

123.

See “Summary of Results, Afrobarometer Round 6, Survey on Liberia, 2015,” Practical Sampling International, Afrobarometer, https://afrobarometer.org/publications/liberia-round-6-summary-results-2015. Afrobarometer considers respondents as “fully demanding democracy” when they explicitly support democracy and reject its alternatives.

124.

The majority of soldiers were inducted in batches 2–5, with smaller classes in batches 1 and 6–8.

125.

Author interview with AFL officer C, Monrovia, July 20, 2017.

126.

Author interview via telephone with former U.S. Embassy official, June 13, 2017.

127.

Mark Malan, Security Sector Reform in Liberia: Mixed Results from Humble Beginnings (Carlisle, Pa.: Strategic Studies Institute, U.S. Army War College Press, 2008), pp. 33–34, https://ssi.armywarcollege.edu/2008/pubs/security-sector-reform-in-liberia-mixed-results-from-humble-beginnings/.

128.

The State Department awarded a contract to DynCorp and Pacific Architects & Engineers to conduct the training, partly because the firms emphasized their commitment to norms training. Author interview with former DynCorp official A, Washington, D.C., June 28, 2017. For detailed accounts of the program, see McFate, Building Better Armies; and Malan, Security Sector Reform in Liberia.

129.

McFate, Building Better Armies, p. 85. Other program architects confirmed this belief. Author interview via Zoom with former DynCorp official C, May 14, 2021.

130.

Ibid.

131.

The State Department ordered DynCorp to pare down the curriculum after batch 1 as a cost-saving measure. Author interview with former DynCorp official B, Monrovia, December 14, 2017. See also McFate, Building Better Armies, p. 87.

132.

Author interview with AFL officers A and B, Monrovia, July 19, 2017.

133.

Author interview with AFL Chief of Staff, Monrovia, July 18, 2017.

134.

Author interview with AFL officers A and B, Monrovia, July 19, 2017.

135.

Batches 1–3 received the entire sequence, from Initial Entry Training through Officer Candidate School, with most soldiers then attending specialized training in the United States. Batches 4–5 had an abridged sequence, with Basic Non-commissioned Officer Course dropping out for officers' training, and fewer soldiers receiving additional training than soldiers in batches 1–3. Author interview with AFL officers A and B, Monrovia, July 19, 2017.

136.

Batches 6–8 did not receive comparable training from any other international actors.

137.

The U.S. military began a mentoring and advising mission, Operation Onward Liberty, in 2010, but the new mission did not provide basic or advanced training.

138.

Author interview with mobile training team members A and B, Monrovia, July 14, 2017. The first Liberian-led OCS class graduated in July 2017, but the Liberian government refused to commission any of the graduates, a decision that U.S. officials felt reflected a lack of confidence in the training.

139.

Robustness tests in the online appendix use an alternative variable specification.

140.

Because two of the outcome measures are binary variables, I run these models using robust standard errors to account for heteroskedasticity. For an alternative specification of a logistic regression model, see the online appendix.

141.

Four respondents either said that they “did not know” or refused to answer this question. Because the “missingness rate” is very low, I dropped these observations from the sample, following Cyrus Samii, “Perils or Promise of Ethnic Integration? Evidence from a Hard Case in Burundi,” American Political Science Review, Vol. 107, No. 3 (2013), p. 566, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055413000282.

142.

Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for this suggestion.

143.

Ellen Johnson Sirleaf and the Unity Party held the presidency in Liberia from 2006 to 2018. The political makeup of the country was consistent between the first and last batches, which helps rule out the possibility that other factors drive this result.

144.

Of the forty-nine respondents, twenty-seven were assigned to the control group and twenty-two to the treatment group.

145.

Powelson, “Enduring Engagement Yes, Episodic Engagement No”; Savage and Caverley, “When Human Capital Threatens the Capitol”; and Biddle, Macdonald, and Baker, “Small Footprint, Small Payoff.”

146.

The variables “education” and “wealth” use standardized language from the Afrobarometer surveys.

147.

The results are robust to an alternative specification as a logistic regression model, reported in the online appendix.

148.

Assignment to the norm conflict treatment was random, which means that the distribution of covariates across treatment and control groups should be similar. Balance statistics, presented in the online appendix, confirm that the distribution of covariates is similar across treatment levels.

149.

For example, all 25,000 applicants to the University of Liberia in 2013 failed the entrance exam because they lacked a “basic grasp of English.” See David Smith, “All 25,000 Candidates Fail Liberian University Entrance Exam,” Guardian, August 27, 2013, https://www.theguardian.com/world/2013/aug/27/all-candidates-fail-liberia-university-test.

150.

The most direct way to mitigate concerns is to include age as a control variable, but this is problematic because age is highly correlated with “batch” (r = 0.52). I excluded age from the primary models but included it in robustness checks reported in the online appendix. The results are largely robust to controlling for age.

151.

Soldiers who want to leave must resort to going absent without leave (AWOL). Author interview via Zoom with former DynCorp official D and former U.S. government official, June 4,2021.

152.

The data show that respondents in the U.S.-trained batches (1 to 5) are somewhat more likely to anticipate leaving the AFL in the next five years, which suggests that commitment to military service is not higher among those remaining in the early batches.

153.

Author interview via Zoom with former DynCorp official C, May 14, 2021; author interview via Zoom with former U.S. military official, May 24, 2021; author interview via Zoom with former DynCorp official D, May 27, 2021; and author interview via Zoom with former DynCorp instructors B and C, June 5, 2021.

154.

Author interview with AFL officer C, Monrovia, July 20, 2017. Nearly two-thirds of the sample disagreed when asked if civilians and the military share a common understanding of civil-military relations in Liberia.

155.

Ibid.

156.

Author interview via Zoom with former DynCorp official B, May 24, 2021; and author interview via Zoom with former U.S. military official, May 24, 2021.

157.

Author interview via Zoom with former DynCorp instructor D, June 12, 2021.

158.

Seminal works include Edward A. Shils and Morris Janowitz, “Cohesion and Disintegration in the Wehrmacht in World War II,” Public Opinion Quarterly, Vol. 12, No. 2 (Summer 1948), pp. 280–315, https://doi.org/10.1086/265950; and Samuel A. Stouffer, The American Soldier (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1949). On approaches to measurement, see Guy L. Siebold, “The Evolution of the Measurement of Cohesion,” Military Psychology, Vol. 11, No. 1 (1999), pp. 526, https://doi.org/10.1207/s15327876mp1101_2.

159.

On the differences between task and social cohesion, see Uzi Ben-Shalom, Zeev Lehrer, and Eyal Ben-Ari, “Cohesion during Military Operations: A Field Study on Combat Units in the Al-Aqsa Intifada,” Armed Forces and Society, Vol. 32, No. 1 (2005), pp. 63–79, https://doi.org/10.1177/0095327X05277888; King, “The Word of Command”; and Siebold, “The Essence of Military Group Cohesion.”

160.

On exclusionary policies and cohesion, see Jason Lyall, Divided Armies: Inequality and Battlefield Performance in Modern War (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2020).

161.

Because the outcome measure is a binary variable, I use logistic regression. See the online appendix for the models used to generate the conditional treatment effects.

162.

A full list of these terms that invoke cohesion is in the online appendix; examples include “here to stay,” “unity,” and “together.”

163.

Another consideration is construct validity, which can be addressed by using different measures and treatments. See Rose McDermott, “Experimental Methodology in Political Science,” Political Analysis, Vol. 10, No. 4 (2002), p. 334, https://doi.org/10.1093/pan/10.4325. The AFL experiment uses an indirect approach to elicit truthful responses, asking soldiers to evaluate the commander's actions. Future experiments could ask soldiers directly how they would respond, which may shed new light on not only norm conflict but also command dynamics.

164.

Susan D. Hyde, “Experiments in International Relations: Lab, Survey, and Field,” Annual Review of Political Science, Vol. 18, No. 1 (2015), pp. 403–424, https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-polisci-020614-094854.

165.

On timing of socialization experiences, see Alastair Iain Johnston, “Conclusions and Extensions: Toward Mid-Range Theorizing and Beyond Europe,” International Organization, Vol. 59, No. 4 (2005), pp. 1013–1044, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020818305050344.

166.

Rose McDermott, “Internal and External Validity,” in James N. Druckman et al., eds., Cambridge Handbook of Experimental Political Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011).

167.

Jason Barabas and Jennifer Jerit, “Are Survey Experiments Externally Valid?,” American Political Science Review, Vol. 104, No. 2 (2010), pp. 226–242, https://doi.org/10.1017/S0003055410000092.

168.

For example, scholars have suggested that even in the United States where civil-military norms are strongly entrenched, a situation in which the military was forced to disobey orders could hollow out norms. See Richard K. Betts and Matthew C. Waxman, “The President and the Bomb: Reforming the Nuclear Launch Process,” Foreign Affairs, Vol. 97, No. 2 (March/April 2018), pp. 121–122, https://www.jstor.org/stable/44822086.

169.

Future research could compare responses to norm conflict among militaries trained primarily by the United States, other liberal providers, and illiberal providers.

170.

African military officers report that up to half of their training time in China comprised classroom indoctrination to Chinese political values. Author discussions with AFL personnel in Monrovia, December 2017.